IDLENESS
IDLENESS
A PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAY
BRIAN OCONNOR
PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS
PRINCETON AND OXFORD
Copyright 2018 by Princeton University Press
Published by Princeton University Press,
41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540
In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press,
6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TR
press.princeton.edu
Jacket image courtesy of Shutterstock
All Rights Reserved
ISBN 978-0-691-16752-7
Library of Congress Control Number: 2018937064
British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available
This book has been composed in Garamond Premier Pro and Arial Rounded
Printed on acid-free paper.
Printed in the United States of America
13579108642
For Jane and Anna
CONTENTS
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
It was a pleasure to work with Ben Tate of Princeton University Press, a source of good judgment ever since our very first discussions on the idea of a book about idleness. Fabian Freyenhagen, Owen Hulatt, Michael Rosen, Liberato Santoro-Brienza, and Tom Stern were kind enough to offer a wide range of challenging criticisms as well as valuable suggestions for texts and passages I might consider. Many of the questions put to me by colleagues at various conferences and colloquia, my own university included, made their mark. Beth Gianfagna copyedited the manuscript with considerable diligence. As ever, though, my greatest debt is to Eileen Brennan for her endless insight and support.
IDLENESS
INTRODUCTION
PHILOSOPHY AND IDLENESS
Questions about the nature of moral values predominate in philosophys analysis of human action. There has been comparatively little concern with bringing to light assumptions about the kinds of people we are supposed to be in order to live as effective and happy actors within the highly integrated and productive societies of today. A moments reflection makes it very clear that fitting in and doing well require us to be madeperhaps even, we might like to think, by our own free choicesinto beings of a very specific and not obviously natural type. Among the key characteristics of this type is a reluctance to idle or a tendency to recognize some wrong in idleness even as we are tempted by it or succumb to it. Philosophers have weighed in with arguments designed to defend negative perceptions of idleness. Traditional moralistic rebukes of the idle are remodeled according to the latest notion of the greatness of humanity. Higher-level narratives about what we truly are or ought to be are offered in explanation of why idleness is not appropriate for beings like us. The aim of this study is to examine and ultimately to expose the presumptions and faults of those narratives.
I will eventually contend that idleness may, in certain respects, be considered closer to the ideals of freedom than the most prestigious conception of self-determination found in philosophy. This book, however, proceeds mainly by way of criticism and without advocacy for the idle life. This is not out of preference for either a superior stance of negativity or scholastic purism. Rather, positive recommendations risk underappreciating how deeply an ambivalence toward idleness is constitutive of much of what many of us take ourselves to be (a point that will be visited many times over the course of this study). That ambivalence will not be resolved by philosophical sketches of a life freed from the driving forces of industry.
Excluding a didactic and constructive approach does not, however, mean that the question of idleness exists here as a strictly theoretical problem.that enable realization of those goods are either only partially available to begin with or are suddenly taken from those who once enjoyed them. Suicide rates increase, families collapse, children struggle. A more stable and less ambitious socioeconomic system could possibly save us from some of the familiar perils of modern life. A bolder image of freedom is, though, offered by idleness. What that would look like in full is another kind of question. But one can conjecture that the genuinely idle would be spared the various forms of pain that are held in store even for those who try to make the most of the twinned institutions of work and social esteem. It is that very intuition that underpins the appeal of idleness even as it sits alongside the winning importance we ultimately attach to those institutions.
The notion of idle freedomwhere work is no kind of virtue or path to worthinessis meaningful and real enough to deserve protection. Here that protection will involve exposing the deficiencies of those many philosophical pronouncements in support of the official view of the world, the view that idleness is a bad, whereas busyness, self-making, usefulness, and productivity are supposedly the very core of what is right for beings like us. Exposing the assumptions and problems of the arguments against idleness might help to preserve the notion of freedom it embodies, even if it is mainly an oppositional freedom: liberation from those unsettling expectations that are all too difficult to resist. The main task of the book, then, will be, in a way, to prevent the philosophical case against idleness from having the last word. And we shall, in fact, see that philosophical accusations do not always lie so very far from more prosaic ones. The worries that, because of idleness, we are in danger of wasting our lives, of not doing justice to ourselves, or simply of not contributing are articulated in systematic and challenging forms in the texts to be considered. Some readers will not agree with my criticisms of those proposals that maintain that human beings are obliged to work toward something so much more impressive than idleness. Others may not believe they actually experience any desire for idlenessthat, at least, is what I am sometimes toldand will therefore be unmoved by efforts in its behalf. This book does not hope to persuade them that they should think otherwise about whether they should develop that desire.
My critical approach could not be accurately described as balanced. I do not proceed with an open mind on whether or not idleness is a bad thing, and I am generally skeptical about any philosophical argument against it. Nevertheless, anti-idleness material is approached in the manner that seems to be expected by its authors. That is, I respond to the arguments found in those texts. I find almost none of them effective, for reasons that will become clear in the course of this book. Nor is my critical approach systematic. My various responses might conceivably amount to the basis of a different conception of work, happiness, or freedom. At this point a cohesive position is not, however, evident. Lastly, what is on offer here is not purely analytical in its dealings with its selected philosophers. Motivations as well as coherence will also be considered.
* * *
Idleness is a complex phenomenon whose meaning varies, sometimes quite radically, across contexts. The notion of idleness I want to explore encapsulates a form of experience that places us outside the norms or conventions of societies like ours. It is not only a state of not working, though that is a key marker. It involves a departure from a range of values that make us the kinds of people we are supposed to be in order to live well. The very idea of being a self of the appropriate kind is thereby placed in question. The features of the phenomenon of idlenessin the sense that is in focus herecan be roughly grouped. First, there are what we may label its
Next page