Dennis J. Schmidt, editor
THE OTHER PLATO
The Tbingen Interpretation of Plato's Inner-Academic Teachings
EDITED BY
DMITRI NIKULIN
STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK PRESS
2012 State University of New York
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher.
For information, contact
State University of New York Press, Albany, NY
www.sunypress.edu
Production, Laurie D. Searl
Marketing, Anne M. Valentine
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
The other Plato : the Tbingen interpretation of Plato's inner-academic teachings / Dmitri Nikulin.
p. cm. (SUNY series in contemporary Continental philosophy)
(SUNY series in ancient Greek philosophy)
Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index.
ISBN 978-1-4384-4409-3 (hardcover : alk. paper)
1. Plato. I. Nikulin, D. V. (Dmitrii Vladimirovich)
B395.O75 2012
184dc23
2011050354
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The essays included in this collection have been previously published as:
H. J. Krmer. : Zu Platon, Politeia 509B. Archiv fr Geschichte der Philosophie 51 (1969): 130.
H. J. Krmer. Platons ungeschriebene Lehre. In Platon: Seine Dialoge in der Sicht der neueren Forschung, ed. T. Kobusch and B. Mojsisch, 249275. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1996.
K. Gaiser. Platons Zusammenschau der mathematischen Wissenschaften. Antike und Abendland 32 (1986): 89124.
Th. A. Szlezk. Die Idee des Guten als arche in Platons Politeia. In New Images of Plato: Dialogues on the Idea of the Good, ed. G. Reale and S. Scolnicov, 4968. Sankt Augustin: Academia, 2000.
J. Halfwassen. Monism and Dualism in Plato's Doctrine of Principles. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 23 (2002): 125144.
V. Hsle. Platons Grundlegung der Euklidizitt der Geometrie. Philologus 126 (1982): 184197; rpt. Platon interpretieren, 145165. Paderborn: Ferdinand Schningh, 2004.
I would like to thank the publishers, Academia Verlag, De Gruyter, Ferdinand Schningh Verlag, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, and the Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal for permission to include translations of the essays in this volume.
I am also grateful to Mitchell Miller and Burt Hopkins for their very helpful comments on the manuscript, to Mario Wenning for exemplary translation of five articles included in this collection, and to Duane Lacey, Erick Raphael Jimnez, and Joseph Lemelin for their help and dedication with the editing of the manuscript. Without their persistence, as well as without the generous support of the Alexander von Humboldt Stiftung in the form of research grants at the universities of Tbingen and Heidelberg, this book could not have been published.
ONE
PLATO: TESTIMONIA ET FRAGMENTA
Dmitri Nikulin
Plato is a unique character among the dramatis personae in the history of philosophy. No other thinker arouses so much emotion and dissent among readers and interpreters. Passions are inevitably stirred when one tries to answer a simple question: What does Plato want to say, and what does he actually say? Plato wrote dialogues, which are fine pieces of literature and reasoning but which may always be read and interpreted differently, especially since the speakers often do not commit themselves to any particular philosophical position and the question discussed frequently remains unanswered and sometimes not even explicitly asked. Moreover, it is neither easy to discern Plato's own position at any given moment in the discussion, nor who is speaking behind his characters. When Socrates is engaged in a dialectical debate of a subject (such as wisdom, courage, love, friendship, temperance, etc.) does he really mean what he says, if one takes into account his undeniably ironic stance? And is it Plato who speaks through Socrates, Socrates himself, or an anonymous voice ascribed to Socrates, made to say what he has to within the logic of the conversation? Plato appears to always escape and defy any final and finalized conclusion, being an Apollo's bird, the swan that, as Socrates predicted, still remains not captured by generations of later readers and interpreters.
Because of the seeming uncertainty of what has actually been said, reading Plato is a fascinating yet risky enterprise, for we might need to reconsider not only our understanding of a text but also the very principles of philosophical reading and interpretation. It is perhaps not by chance that modern hermeneutics arises with Schleiermacher and flourishes in Gadamer as primarily an attempt to make sense of the Platonic dialogues, of their intention and proper sense. Yet, since the dialogues appear to be open to a variety of consistent but mutually conflicting interpretations, reading them leads to so much disagreement, misunderstanding, and even mutual mistrust in the guild of fellow Plato scholars.
THE TBINGEN SCHOOL
Among recent notable attempts to provide a different reading of Plato is the so-called Tbingen interpretation, both an original attempt at reading and understanding Plato, and at the same time one rooted in a philological and philosophical tradition that goes back to the end of the eighteenth century while echoing Platonic (Neoplatonic) interpretations of Plato. This interpretation of Plato originated in the works of two students of Wolfgang Schadewaldt, Hans Joachim Krmer and Konrad Gaiser, who were also joined by Heinz Happ, Thomas A. Szlezk, Jrgen Wippern, and later by Vittorio Hsle and Jens Halfwassen. In Italy, Giovanni Reale became the main proponent of the Tbingen interpretation, and in France, Marie-Dominique Richard. The two path-breaking works were Platons ungeschriebene Lehre, which were followed by a number of other relevant publications.
The Tbingen reconstruction attempts to provide a systematic understanding of Plato based on the evidence preserved in the tradition of the transmission and interpretation of his texts. Dietrich Tiedemann and especially Wilhelm Gottlieb Tennemann, both of whom predate the Romantic reading of Plato and still continue the line of Neoplatonic interpretation, had already argued in favor of the existence of a systematic oral teaching in Plato. It is because of this tradition, which pays attention to the evidence preserved in earlier philosophical works and stresses the necessity of meticulous philological research oriented toward a philosophical understanding of the text, that we now have Diels and Kranz's Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. It is this tradition that made such a profound impact on ancient scholarship of the nineteenth century, including Jacob Burckhardt and Nietzsche, and the whole of twentieth-century Continental philosophy, including the Neo-Kantians, Heidegger, Hannah Arendt, and Hans Jonas.