• Complain

Ferber Ilit - Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking

Here you can read online Ferber Ilit - Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. City: New York, Dordrecht, year: 2011, publisher: Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Ferber Ilit Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking
  • Book:
    Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2011
  • City:
    New York, Dordrecht
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Philosophys Moods is a collection of original essays interrogating the inseparable bond between mood and philosophical thinking. What is the relationship between mood and thinking in philosophy? In what sense are we always already philosophizing from within a mood? What kinds of mood are central for shaping the space of philosophy? What is the philosophical imprint of Aristotles wonder, Kants melancholy, Kierkegaards anxiety or Nietzsches shamelessness? Philosophys Moods invites its readers to explore the above questions through diverse methodological perspectives. Read more...
Abstract: Philosophys Moods is a collection of original essays interrogating the inseparable bond between mood and philosophical thinking. It offers the first systematic and comprehensive contribution to the contemporary philosophical debate on the nature of moods. Read more...

Ferber Ilit: author's other books


Who wrote Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Part 1
INTRODUCTION
Hagi Kenaan and Ilit Ferber (eds.) Contributions To Phenomenology Philosophy's Moods: The Affective Grounds of Thinking 10.1007/978-94-007-1503-5_1 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011
Moods and Philosophy
Hagi Kenaan 1
(1)
Department of Philosophy, Tel-Aviv University, 39040, Ramat Aviv, Tel-Aviv, 69978, Israel
Hagi Kenaan (Corresponding author)
Email:
Ilit Ferber
Email:
Abstract
Jean-Paul Sartres novel Nausea , presented as the journal of Antoine Roquentin, opens with the narrators statement of an unexplained change that has pervaded his world. Roquentins need to examine this disturbing sense of change is the explicit reason why he begins writing.
I.Toward a Phenomenology of Moods
Jean-Paul Sartres novel Nausea , presented as the journal of Antoine Roquentin, opens with the narrators statement of an unexplained change that has pervaded his world. Roquentins need to examine this disturbing sense of change is the explicit reason why he begins writing.
The best thing would be to write down events from day to day. Keep a diary to see clearlylet none of the nuances or small happenings escape even though they might seem to mean nothing. And above all, classify them. I must tell how I see this table, this street, the people, my packet of tobacco, since those are the things which have changed. I must determine the exact extent and nature of this change. (Sartre : 1)
Roquentin searches for an understanding by attending to the manifestations of the ordinary. Through close attention to the ordinary, he seeks to articulate the manner in which his whole being-in-the-world has changed.
For instance, there is something new about my hands, a certain way of picking up my pipe or fork. Or else its the fork which now has a certain way of having itself picked up, I dont know. A little while ago, just as I was coming into my room, I stopped short because I felt in my hand a cold object which held my attention through a sort of personality. I opened my hand, looked: I was simply holding the door-knob. (Sartre : 4)
Roquentin is unaware of the phenomenological resonance and philosophical potential of his detailed daily descriptions. He is thus somewhat surprised when, his inspection of experience reveals to him the world itself, the world of which he is part, rather than a private mental domain. The unmistakable presence of a new quality acquired by the world or, perhaps, the new absence of a dimension that has unexpectedly vanished from the world makes it difficult for Roquentin to find the terms to pinpoint the change he has experienced.
So a change has taken place during these last few weeks. But where? It is an abstract change without object. Am I the one who has changed? If not, then it is this room, this city and this nature; I must choose. (Sartre : 4)
Yet, despite his intentions, Roquentin is ultimately unable to choose between the internal and external, since the very opposition between the two realms cannot do justice to his experience. Roquentins world has changed in a manner that does not lend itself to an understanding in terms of a mere subjective occurrence. At the same time, however, Roquentin is unable to frame the change in terms of the objective state of things, e.g., in terms of objects and their properties. It is an abstract change without object, one that cannot register within the objective order of facts. Roquentins difficulty is, in itself, revealing.
Roquentin is ultimately concerned only with the specificity of his own situation, i.e., with a mood that reveals the bare such-ness of the world and bears a distinctive affect of nausea. Yet, despite his focus on a specific mood, Roquentins explorations inadvertently provide a few important insights into the more general structure of moods. His ability to identify a transformation in the quality and form of his experience of the world, together with the inability to explain this transformation in terms of the common opposition between the subjective and the objective, is indeed indicative of the unique manner in which moods are present in our lives.
As a corollary we may say, with Heidegger, that moods are world revealing. For Heidegger, a central figure in this collection and clearly the most important twentieth-century advocate for moods, Dasein always belongs to a world; but this world is neither the totality of objective facts nor a merely subjective experience. World is rather the human realm of meaningfulness that precedes the distinction between the subjective and the objective. Our embeddedness in the world, our basic attachment to meaning, finds its primary expression in the experience of the world as that which matters to us: in moods.
With a new friend around, the city that seemed so gloomy now appears joyful and vibrant. Indeed, the world matters to us in different ways, at different times revealed through the changes of moods that are, concomitantly, a disclosure of moods dynamic infrastructure. Like Roquentin, we know that moods change, but their constant flux indicates more than their plurality and transitional nature. Change is the primary manner in which moods or the spectrum of moods is revealed to us. What their constant movement signifies is that moods are always already there, operative in this form or another in structuring our encounter with the world. As Heidegger puts it, We are never free of moods . A state-of-mind always has its understanding understanding always has its mood (Heidegger : 182 [143]).
According to Heidegger, moods precede any form of cognition and, moreover, they condition it. Mood is a primordial kind of Being for Dasein, in which Dasein is disclosed to itself prior to all cognition and volition, and beyond their range of disclosure (Heidegger : 232, H187).
Moods are crucial for an understanding of our being-in-the-world; however, are moods also pertinent to an understanding of the distinctly philosophical openness to the world? What is it about moods that makes them specifically important to phenomenology?
Since Husserl, phenomenology has consistently singled itself out by making a point of its point of entry into reflection. Phenomenological reflection is dependent on, and cannot begin without, an essential transformation of our ordinary gaze. This transformation or alteration of the natural attitude is not a trivial aspect but constitutes a moment wherein resides much of the difficulty of practicing the phenomenological method . For Husserl, The phenomenological epoch lays open an infinite realm of being of a new kind , as the sphere of a new kind of experience: transcendental experience (Husserl : 20).
What the phenomenologist acquires by this universal depriving of acceptance, inhibiting or putting out of play of all positions taken toward the already given objective world is the universe of phenomena in the phenomenological sense (Husserl : 2021). Phenomenology, in other words, not only begins with a crucial shift away from our ordinary immersion in the world; it is, moreover, dependent on the possibility we have as humans of dodging or disconnecting ourselves from the claims of the ordinary world to which we are typically riveted. The epoch is a constitutive moment in the phenomenological response to the world, one that opens up the world as a phenomenological field by finding a new distance within our ordinary proximity to things. This distancing is of course different in many ways from the new experience, the transformation, that Sartres Roquentin seeks to account for. But, at the same time, the epoch , read against the background of Roquentins insights, raises the question whether the possibility of the epoch and thus of phenomenology in general is not couched in the very structure of mood.
Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking»

Look at similar books to Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking»

Discussion, reviews of the book Philosophys moods : the affective grounds of thinking and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.