Routledge Revivals
Our Knowledge of the Growth of Knowledge
Peter Munz, a former student of both Popper and Wittgenstein, begins his comparison of the two great twentieth-century philosophers by explaining that since the demise of positivism there have emerged, broadly speaking, two philosophical options: Wittgenstein, with the absolute relativism of his theory that meaning is a function of language games and that social configurations are determinants of knowledge; and Poppers evolutionary epistemology conscious knowledge is a special case of the relationship which exists between all living beings and their environments.
Professor Munz examines and rejects the Wittgensteinian position. Instead, Our Knowledge of the Growth of Knowledge , first published in 1985, elaborates the potentially fruitful link between Poppers critical rationalism and Neo-Darwinism. Read in the light of the latter, Poppers philosophy leads to the transformation of Kants Transcendental Idealism into Hypothetical Realism, whilst the emphasis on the biological orientation of Poppers thought helps to illumine some difficulties in Poppers falsificationism.
Our Knowledge of the Growth of Knowledge
Popper or Wittgenstein?
Peter Munz
First published in 1985
by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd
This edition first published in 2014 by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
1985 Peter Munz
The right of Peter Munz to be identified as author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Publishers Note
The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but points out that some imperfections in the original copies may be apparent.
Disclaimer
The publisher has made every effort to trace copyright holders and welcomes correspondence from those they have been unable to contact.
A Library of Congress record exists under LC control number: 85001730
ISBN 13: 978-1-138-77867-2 (hbk)
ISBN 13: 978-1-315-77171-7 (ebk)
Additional materials are available on the companion website at
[http://www.routledge.com/books/series/Routledge_Revivals]
PETER MUNZ
Our Knowledge of the Growth of Knowledge
Popper or Wittgenstein?
ROUTLEDGE & KEGAN PAUL
London, Boston, Melbourne and Henley
First published in 1985
by Routledge & Kegan Paul plc
14 Leicester Square, London WC2H 7PH, England
9 Park Street, Boston, Mass. 02108, USA
464 St Kilda Road, Melbourne,
Victoria 3004, Australia and
Broadway House, Newtown Road,
Henley on Thames, Oxon RG9 I EN, England
Set in Baskerville
by Hope Services Ltd, Abingdon
and printed in Great Britain by
Billings and Sons Ltd,
Worcester
Peter Munz 1985
No part of this book may be reproduced in
any form without permission from the publisher,
except for the quotation of brief passages
in criticism
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Munz, Peter, 1921
Our knowledge of the growth of knowledge Includes index.
1. Knowledge, Theory of. 2. Popper, Karl Raimund, Sir, 1902 . 3 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 18891951.
I. Title
BD161.M86 1985 121 851730
British Library CIP data also available
ISBN 0-7102-0460-4
Contents
This book is an attempt to explore some special consequences of one of the greatest changes which have come over our view of the world. Until not so very long ago we believed that nature was steady and unchanging, without a history; and that human culture had a history but that that history was not part of the steady existence of nature but more like an ephemeral dance performed on natures stage. In our new view of the world which has firmly established itself in the course of the twentieth century, nature and history have come together. Nature herself, we have come to see, has a history and human history is inserted into it. Thus, there must be some kind of link between the historicity of nature and the historicity of man. The history of nature influences the history of man; and the history of man, in the shape of mans knowledge of nature, in turn, reflects upon the history of nature. If there still are two cultures the extension of historicity has made their practitioners realise that they have a lot in common.
Unfortunately, the clarity of this vision tends to be clouded when we expect too much from our knowledge of history. It is one thing to be aware of the historicity of nature and of man. But it does not follow that we can be equally certain of the actual course of these histories. On the contrary, historical knowledge is subject to the same doubts and uncertainties as all knowledge and cannot be used to establish any final view about the growth of knowledge, let alone firm thoughts about a lack of growth or about the finality of the relativism of all knowledge.
In writing this book I was very much the beady-eyed historian who seeks to explain the limitations of historical knowledge and the conditions it is subject to. Bearing those limitations in mind, I am arguing in favour of a philosophy of knowledge which, while encompassing the historicity both of nature and of man, does not depend on historical knowledge alone. Again, writing as a historian I have little interest in conceptual analysis. The form of discourse I employ is not coercive, but explanatory in Robert Nozicks sense. But unlike Nozick I do not believe that any explanation can be self-explanatory. On the contrary: in explaining I have to have constant recourse to a theory in terms of which any explanation holds good. In this case, the theory in question is the theory of evolution and for the purposes of this book, that theory is itself not a subject to be explained. However, lest the reader think that in saying that all explanations are relative to a theory I am subscribing to Richard Rortys view that all truths and meanings are relative to a speech community or a tradition of rhetoric, I wish to state that I hold the opposite view. In saying that explanations are never absolute but always in terms of something else, I mean that whatever they are relative to must, in turn and on a different occasion, be open to criticism and be explained.
Not counting the Introduction, the book falls into three parts. In the first part () I return to the main theme by developing Karl Poppers evolutionary philosophy of knowledge and by sketching the major transformations of thought which become possible and desirable when one takes historicity seriously.
The shape of my argument is almost wholly dependent on the fact that I was a student of Karl Popper in Christchurch, New Zealand (19404) and of Wittgenstein in Cambridge (19468). At the time these early influences were the result of accidents: I had come to Christchurch as a refugee from the Second World War, and to Cambridge to study medieval history. There was no plan to learn from either Popper or Wittgenstein and it took me several decades to discover how this educational accident came to be turned into a fundamental and meaningful philosophical experience. I have since recorded this extraordinary accident in a paper on Transformation in Philosophy through the Teaching Methods of Wittgenstein and Popper ( Proceedings of the Tenth International Conference on the Unity of the Sciences , New York, 1982, vol. 2, pp. 123565).