• Complain

Josef Pieper - Leisure: The Basis of Culture

Here you can read online Josef Pieper - Leisure: The Basis of Culture full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 1998, publisher: St. Augustine’s Press, genre: Science. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Josef Pieper Leisure: The Basis of Culture

Leisure: The Basis of Culture: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Leisure: The Basis of Culture" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

One of the most important philosophy titles published in the twentieth century, Josef PiepersLeisure: the Basis of Cultureis more significant, even more crucial, today than it was when it first appeared fifty years ago. Pieper shows that the Greeks understood and valued leisure, as did the medieval Europeans. He points out that religion can be born only in leisure - a leisure that allows time for the contemplation of the nature of God. Leisure has been, and always will be, the first foundation of any culture.
He maintains that our bourgeois world of total labor has vanquished leisure, and issues a startling warning: Unless we regain the art of silence and insight, the ability for nonactivity, unless we substitute true leisure for our hectic amusements, we will destroy our culture - and ourselves.
These astonishing essays contradict all our pragmatic and puritanical conceptions about labor and leisure; Josef Pieper demolishes the twentieth-century cult of work as he predicts its destructive consequences.

Josef Pieper: author's other books


Who wrote Leisure: The Basis of Culture? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Leisure: The Basis of Culture — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Leisure: The Basis of Culture" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Leisure, the Basis of Culture

Leisure

The Basis of Culture

Josef Pieper Introduction by Roger Scruton New translation by Gerald Malsbary - photo 1

Josef Pieper

Introduction by Roger Scruton

New translation by Gerald Malsbary

St Augustines Press South Bend Indiana 1998 Copyright 1948 by Ksel-Verlag - photo 2

St. Augustines Press

South Bend, Indiana

1998

Copyright Picture 3 1948 by Ksel-Verlag

Translation copyright Picture 4 1998 by St. Augustines Press, Inc.

Originally published in German as Musse und Kult and Was heisst Philosophieren?

by Ksel-Verlag. Authors preface is from the first English edition, published by Pantheon Books, a division of Random House, Inc.

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of St. Augustines Press.

Manufactured in the United States of America.

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data

Pieper, Josef, 1904 - 1997

[Musse und Kult. English] Leisure, the basis of culture / Josef Pieper: introduction by

Roger Scruton; new translation by Gerald Malsbary.

p. cm.

Consists of a translation of the authors Musse und Kult, and of his Was heisst Philosophieren?

Includes bibliographical references.

ISBN 1-890318-35-3 (pbk. : alk. paper)

1. Leisure. 2. God - Worship and love. 3. Culture. 4. Philosophy. I. Malsbary, Gerald. II. Pieper, Josef, 1904 - 1997 Was heisst Philosophieren? English. III. Title.

BJ1498.P513 1998 175 - dc21

98-15340 CIP

4 5 6 7 8 9 10 10 09 08 07 06 05 04 03

The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences - Permanence of Paper for Printed Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1984.

Table of Contents

INTRODUCTION
by T. S. Eliot

The complaint is frequently heard that our time has little to boast of in the way of philosophy. Whether this deficiency is due to some ailment of philosophy itself, or to the diversion of able philosophical minds towards other studies, or simply to a shortage of philosophers, is never made clear: these are divisions of the question which are apt to become confused. Certainly, Where are the great philosophers? is a rhetorical question often asked by those who pursued their philosophical studies forty or fifty years ago. Allowing for the possibility that the great figures of our youth have become magnified by the passage of time, and for the probability that most of those who ask the question have not followed modern philosophical developments very closely, there remains some justification of the lament. It may be merely a longing for the appearance of a philosopher whose writings, lectures and personality will arouse the imagination as Bergson, for instance, aroused it forty years ago; but it may be also the expression of a need for philosophy in an older meaning of the word the need for new authority to express insight and wisdom.

To those who pine for philosophy in this ampler sense, logical positivism is the most conspicuous object of censure. Certainly, logical positivism is not a very nourishing diet for more than the small minority which has been conditioned to it. When the time of its exhaustion arrives, it will probably appear, in retrospect, to have been for our age the counterpart of surrealism: for as surrealism seemed to provide a method of producing works of art without imagination, so logical positivism seems to provide a method of philosophizing without insight and wisdom. The attraction which it thus offers to the immature mind may have unfortunate results for some of those who pursue their undergraduate studies under its influence. Yet I believe that in the longer view, logical positivism will have proved of service by explorations of thought which we shall, in future, be unable to ignore; and even if some of its avenues turn out to be blind alleys, it is, after all, worth while exploring a blind alley, if only to discover that it is blind. And, what is more important for my theme, I believe that the sickness of philosophy, an obscure recognition of which moves those who complain of its decline, has been present too long to be attributable to any particular contemporary school of thought.

At the time when I myself was a student of philosophy I speak of a period some thirty-five to forty years ago the philosopher was beginning to suffer from a feeling of inferiority to the exact scientist. It was felt that the mathematician was the man best qualified to philosophize. Those students of philosophy who had not come to philosophy from mathematics did their best (at least, in the university in which my studies were conducted) to try to become imitation mathematicians at least to the extent of acquainting themselves with the paraphernalia of symbolic logic. (I remember one enthusiastic contemporary who devised a Symbolic Ethics, for which he had to invent several symbols not found in the Principia Mathematica.) Beyond this, some familiarity with contemporary physics and with contemporary biology was also prized: a philosophical argument supported by illustrations from one of these sciences was more respectable than one which lacked them even if the supporting evidence was sometimes irrelevant. Now I am quite aware that to the philosopher no field of knowledge should come amiss. The ideal philosopher would be at ease with every science, with every branch of art, with every language, and with the whole of human history. Such encyclopaedic knowledge might preserve him from excessive awe of those disciplines in which he was untrained, and excessive bias towards those in which he was well exercised. But in an age in which every branch of study becomes more subdivided and specialized, the ideal of omniscience is more and more remote from realization. Yet only omniscience is enough, once the philosopher begins to rely upon science. No one today, I imagine, would follow the example of Bosanquet, who in his Logic leant so heavily upon illustrations drawn from Linnaean Botany. But while the philosophers exploitation of science is now likely to meet with severe criticism, we are perhaps too ready to accept the conclusions of the scientist when he philosophizes.

One effect of this striving of philosophy towards the condition of the exact sciences was that it produced the illusion of a progress of philosophy, of a kind to which philosophy should not pretend. It turned out philosophical pedagogues ignorant, not merely of history in the general sense, but of the history of philosophy itself. If our attitude towards philosophy is influenced by an admiration for the exact sciences, then the philosophy of the past is something that has been superseded. It is punctuated by individual philosophers, some of whom had moments of understanding, but whose work as a whole comes to be regarded as quaint and primitive. For the philosophy of the present, from this point of view, is altogether better than that of the past, when science was in its infancy; and the philosophy of the future will proceed from the discoveries of our own age. It is true that the history of philosophy is now admitted as a branch of study in itself, and that there are specialists in this subject: but I suspect that in the opinion of a philosopher of the modern school, the historian of philosophy is rather an historian than a philosopher.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Leisure: The Basis of Culture»

Look at similar books to Leisure: The Basis of Culture. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Leisure: The Basis of Culture»

Discussion, reviews of the book Leisure: The Basis of Culture and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.