First published in 1968
This edition first published in 2015
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
1968 Y. Murakami
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
ISBN: 978-0-415-72731-0 (Set)
eISBN: 978-1-315-76997-4 (Set)
ISBN: 978-1-138-78426-0 (Volume 40)
eISBN: 978-1-315-76353-8 (Volume 40)
Publishers Note
The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but points out that some imperfections in the original copies may be apparent.
Disclaimer
The publisher has made every effort to trace copyright holders and would welcome correspondence from those they have been unable to trace.
First published 1968
in Great Britain by
Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd
Broadway House, 6874 Carter Lane
London, E.C.4
and in the USA by
Dover Publications Inc
180 Varick Street
New York, 10014
Y. Murakami 1968
No part of this book may be reproduced
in any form without permission from
the publisher, except for the quotation
of brief passages in criticism
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 6726965
SBN 7100 2981 0
Printed in Great Britain
by Richard Clay (The Chaucer Press), Ltd.,
Bungay, Suffolk
A society consists of individual members and a societys decision is composed of its members decisions. Each society has its own rule for making decisions. When a combination of individual decisions is given, a societys decision is reached according to that rule. Probably the most familiar example of a social decision-making rule is voting. By casting a ballot, each individual expresses his decision on the issue in question, say, an election where a Conservative candidate and a Labour candidate are contesting a seat in Parliament. Society adopts the decision supported by the majority of voters; thus, if the Conservative candidate obtains more votes, he is the social choice. Once a pattern of individual decisions is formed, the rule of majority voting yields a social decision. As the pattern changes, the social decision also varies. The mathematician, as well as the logician, would say that a social decision is a function of individual decisions, in the sense that a combination of individual decisions determines a social decision. More formally, we may express this as
R = F (R1, R2, , Rn)
where R and Rj are variables for the decisions of the society and of the jth individual respectively, n being the number of individuals. The function F represents societys rule for decision-making, so we may call this function the social decision function.
Any change in a social decision can occur only through changes in individual decisions. Thus, by the formulation presented above we can express any social decision-making rule. Sometimes, as in the case of religious taboos, a social decision may be traditionally fixed, regardless of changes in individual decisions. However, a traditionally fixed social decision is still a function of individual decisions, in the sense that the function takes on a constant value. In some societies, a particular individual may be so powerful that his decision is always adopted by the society. In other words, the individual is a dictator. But this dictatorial rule of social decision-making constitutes simply a special class of social decision function; individuals other than the dictator can be deleted from the function. Whether a society is traditional, dictatorial or democratic, which we shall investigate later, the social decision function as defined above is sufficiently general to express any form of social decision.
From a psychological point of view, an individual decision is a complex phenomenon. Hedonist psychology assumes that an individual decision is a revelation of the persons desire, satisfaction, pleasure, taste or whatever the philosopher or social scientist wishes to call it. Many economic analyses, as well as the utilitarian philosophy behind them, are known to be based on a similar view. On the other hand, many people argue that the exercise of individual desire is restrained by some idealistic principle, or perhaps by some subconscious motivation. The question of how and why individual decisions are made belongs to the field of psychology.
Throughout this book we shall be concerned with the behaviouristic rather than the motivational aspect of decision making. By an individual decision we mean simply that the individual behaves as if he had a definite order of preference concerning the alternatives open to him. Whatever his motivations, the individual behaves as if he had arranged, in his mind, all the conceivable alternatives, in order of preference, when he makes a decision. This is our definition of individual decision.
Mr. Smith, a citizen in a Midwest town, prefers a Republican candidate to a Democratic candidate for some reason of his own. This is his decision. Mr. Jones, a gentleman in North Devon, prefers a Liberal candidate to a Conservative candidate, and a Conservative candidate to a Labour candidate. Various motivations prompt Mr. Jones to make this decision. One of the most fundamental assumptions of economics is that a consumer orders all possible expenditure plans according to his preference. The well-known indifference map is a device to describe visually a consumers ordering. Each individuals indifference map reveals his decision.
Throughout this book, we shall generally regard an individuals decision as equivalent to his preference, represented as an ordering, or, in short, to his preference ordering. It must be noted, however, that a distinction between preference and decision is sometimes meaningful. For an individual may sometimes purposely misrepresent his preference ordering. Once a social decision-making rule is given, an individual might find it profitable to misrepresent his preference in action. That is, he might act insincerely. We shall assume in this book, however, that every individual is sincere or, in other words, that every individuals decision is identical with his preference. This is one of the limitations of this book.
However, we shall later present () a condition under which no misrepresentation of individual preference is profitable. We shall see that this condition is satisfied by many social decision functions familiar to us; so we may sometimes be justified in assuming individual sincerity. Only in that section, are decision and preference to be carefully distinguished. Otherwise, both terms will be employed interchangeably.