• Complain

Horská - Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals

Here you can read online Horská - Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2014, publisher: Springer, genre: Children. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Horská Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals
  • Book:
    Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Springer
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2014
  • Rating:
    5 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 100
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

This book explains the first published consistency proof of PA. It contains the original Gentzens proof, but it uses modern terminology and examples to illustrate the essential notions. The author comments on Gentzens steps which are supplemented with exact calculations and parts of formal derivations. A notable aspect of the proof is the representation of ordinal numbers that was developed by Gentzen. This representation is analysed and connection to set-theoretical representation is found, namely an algorithm for translating Gentzens notation into Cantor normal form. The topic should interest researchers and students who work on proof theory, history of proof theory or Hilberts program and who do not mind reading mathematical texts. Read more...
Abstract: This book explains the first published consistency proof of PA. It contains the original Gentzens proof, but it uses modern terminology and examples to illustrate the essential notions. The author comments on Gentzens steps which are supplemented with exact calculations and parts of formal derivations. A notable aspect of the proof is the representation of ordinal numbers that was developed by Gentzen. This representation is analysed and connection to set-theoretical representation is found, namely an algorithm for translating Gentzens notation into Cantor normal form. The topic should interest researchers and students who work on proof theory, history of proof theory or Hilberts program and who do not mind reading mathematical texts

Horská: author's other books


Who wrote Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Anna Horsk SpringerBriefs in Philosophy Where is the Gdel-point hiding: Gentzens Consistency Proof of 1936 and His Representation of Constructive Ordinals 2014 10.1007/978-3-319-02171-3_1
The Author(s) 2014
1. Introduction
Anna Horsk 1
(1)
Department of Logic, Charles University in Prague, Prague, Czech Republic
Anna Horsk
Email:
Abstract
This chapter deals with brief history of Gentzens consistency proofs and his work on proof systems which were actually byproducts of his ambition to prove the consistency of arithmetic. There is a plan in his handwritten thesis manuscript according to which he aimed to prove the consistency with the help of normalization for natural deduction. As this did not work, he developed a special semantic explanation of correctness in arithmetic. The proof based on this explanation was criticized, so Gentzen returned to an earlier idea of transfinite induction. The last proof shows directly that although the transfinite induction up to Picture 1 can be formalized in arithmetic, it cannot be proved there. Further, this chapter deals with non-technical parts of his 1936 article.
Keywords
Gentzen Gentzens thesis Proof systems Consistency proofs Consistency proofs of arithmetic History of proof systems History of consistency proofs Consistency of arithmetic Hilberts program
The trust in intuitively obvious axioms was destroyed after the discovery of paradoxes in naive set theory at the beginning of the twentieth century. Intuitions dealing with actual infinity, especially, turned out to be misleading and it was necessary to deal with them in a more careful way. On the one hand, Brouwers intuitionism regards mathematics as a languageless, constructive, mental activity and intuitions of the idealized mind should reflect on which constructions are allowed. On the other hand, formalism uses axiomatic systems for mathematical investigations, but tries to eliminate all intuitions form them. This is possible in the way that all meanings are removed from an axiomatic system except for such meanings that can be defined according to the rules of the system itself. The system should be examined regardless of its interpretation. The German mathematician David Hilbert is considered to be the major proponent of formalism. He proposed a research project around 1920, today known as Hilberts program, which was meant as an answer to the crisis brought on by the paradoxes in naive set theory. He aimed to establish secure foundations for all mathematics by grounding all theories on a finite set of axioms and schemata whose consistency should have been proved by finitistic methods. These methods were regarded as reliable and the consistency of the classical mathematics proved with the help of these methods would have provided a justification for non-intuitive parts of the field, especially the parts dealing with actual infinity.
In general, consistency proofs are classified into two groups: absolute and relative consistency proofs. Whereas an absolute consistency proof does not presuppose the consistency of some other system, a relative consistency proof reduces the consistency of a theory Picture 2 to the consistency of another theory Picture 3 . Thus, we demand a consistency proof for Picture 4 . In this way, we can obtain a potentially infinite hierarchy of theories. Anyway, we need a theory at the beginning of this hierarchy whose consistency can by proved without any reference to another theory, in other words, a theory which has an absolute consistency proof. It seemed that arithmetic is so fundamental that its consistency might be proved within the finitistic methods. This would suffice to regard it as an absolute consistency proof. In late 1930, Gdels incompleteness theorems became known and it was clear that even the tools of arithmetic itself would not suffice to obtain its consistency.
Gerhard Gentzen was a student of Paul Bernays. In early 1932, he set out to work on the consistency of arithmetic. The role of Bernays in this decision of his is not known, but as Gentzen wrote in a letter to Professor Hellmuth Kneser in December 1932 (Menzler-Trott , p. 315):
The axioms of arithmetic are obviously correct, and the principles of proof obviously preserve correctness. Why cannot one simply conclude consistency, i.e., what is the true meaning of the second incompleteness theorem, the one by which the consistency of arithmetic cannot be proved by arithmetic means? Where is the Gdel-point hiding?
In contrast to his predecessors (Frege, Russell), Gentzen was not looking for absolute mathematical truth. He focused on how mathematical theorems are proved in practice, i.e., how one derives a conclusion from given assumptions. The first step he made was that he put aside prevailing proof systems of logicism whose linear derivations did not fit in with the idea of actual mathematical proofs because their starting points were basic logical truths and rules of inference just generated further truths. Gentzens examination of actual reasoning ended in natural deduction calculus whose derivations were in the form of trees. He was probably inspired by Paul Hertz (), whose work he had been studied at the suggestion of Bernays in 1931, when he came up with the tree derivations. Although the tree derivations are in fact a departure form actual proofs, they have some technical advantages over the linear derivations: One can permute the order of rules and compose different derivations without losing a full control over the structure of the result.
The following plan is in Gentzens handwritten thesis manuscript (von Plato , p. 336):
I.
To put up the calculus of natural deduction.
II.
To prove that it is equivalent to standard axiomatic calculi.
III.
To prove that classical arithmetic reduces to intuitionistic arithmetic.
IV.
To prove normalization.
V.
To extend normalization and the subformula property to arithmetic.
Let us explain the items:
I.
The calculi of natural deduction, Picture 5 for classical and Picture 6 for intuitionistic logic, were completed by September 1932. There are several possibilities which might have led Gentzen to the rules of these calculi. It is known that Gentzen studied Heytings formalization of intuitionistic logic (Heyting , p. 322). His natural deduction calculus originally contained an induction rule. It means that Gentzen was definitely interested in arithmetic.
II.
Gentzen translated derivations in natural deduction into the axiomatic logical calculus of Hilbert and Ackermanns book (Hilbert and Ackermann ) and back.
III.
The third task was accomplished by the Gdel-Gentzen translation which was almost simultaneously developed by both mathematicians after whom it is called. The translation embeds classical arithmetic into intuitionistic one. The result is that it suffices to prove the consistency of intuitionistic arithmetic which would assure that classical arithmetic is consistent, too. We will see that Gentzens plan failed in the item V., so he submitted this result as a separate article to the Mathematische Annalen in March 1933. Then he withdrew the paper because the same result by Gdel ().
Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals»

Look at similar books to Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals»

Discussion, reviews of the book Where is the Gödel-point hiding : Gentzens consistency proof of 1936 and his representation of constructive ordinals and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.