• Complain

Keith J. Bybee - All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law

Here you can read online Keith J. Bybee - All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2010, publisher: Stanford University Press, genre: Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Keith J. Bybee All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law
  • Book:
    All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Stanford University Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2010
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

We live in an age where one persons judicial activist legislating from the bench is anothers impartial arbiter fairly interpreting the law. After the Supreme Court ended the 2000 Presidential election with its decision in Bush v. Gore, many critics claimed that the justices had simply voted their political preferences. But Justice Clarence Thomas, among many others, disagreed and insisted that the Court had acted according to legal principle, stating: I plead with you, that, whatever you do, dont try to apply the rules of the political world to this institution; they do not apply.The legitimacy of our courts rests on their capacity to give broadly acceptable answers to controversial questions. Yet Americans are divided in their beliefs about whether our courts operate on unbiased legal principle or political interest. Comparing law to the practice of common courtesy, Keith Bybee explains how our courts not only survive under these suspicions of hypocrisy, but actually depend on them.Law, like courtesy, furnishes a means of getting along. It frames disputes in collectively acceptable ways, and it is a habitual practice, drummed into the minds of citizens by popular culture and formal institutions. The rule of law, thus, is neither particularly fair nor free of paradoxical tensions, but it endures. Although pervasive public skepticism raises fears of judicial crisis and institutional collapse, such skepticism is also an expression of how our legal system ordinarily functions.

Keith J. Bybee: author's other books


Who wrote All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

THE CULTURAL LIVES OF LAW

Edited by Austin Sarat

All Judges Are PoliticalExcept When They Are Not

Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law

Keith Bybee

Stanford University Press
Stanford, California

2010 by the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. All rights reserved.

No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of Stanford University Press.

Printed in the United States of America on acid-free, archival-quality paper

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Bybee, Keith J., 1965

All judges are politicalexcept when they are not : acceptable hypocrisies and the rule of law / Keith J. Bybee.

p. cm.

Includes bibliographical references and index.

9780804775618

1. Judicial processUnited States. 2. Political questions and judicial powerUnited States. 3. Rule of lawUnited States. I. Title.

KF8775.B93 2010

347.7312dc22

2010011546

Typeset by Classic Typography in 11/13.5 Adobe Garamond

For Jennifer, Evan, and Ava

Table of Contents


Part I

Legal Realism: Dead and Alive

IN THE WINTER OF 2003, THE NEW YORK TIMES announced the triumph of legal realism, the theory that suggests judicial decisionmaking is essentially a matter of politics. Spargos political enthusiasm earned him a judicial promotion. In 2001, he was elected to the State Supreme Court in Albany County.

Spargos politicking was less popular in other quarters. The New York State Commission on Judicial Conduct charged Spargo with violating the state rules governing judicial behavior. In response, Spargo filed suit claiming that the state code of judicial conduct was unconstitutional. The federal district court agreed. Applying the United States Supreme Court decision Republican Party of Minnesota v. White , the court ruled that Spargo was free to be as politically active as he had been.

Interestingly enough, Spargo himself was among the first to call legal realisms victory into question. Although he thought that the ruling was absolutely good because it freed judges to be more involved in the political life of their communities, he otherwise believed that the decision pushed a political understanding of the courts too far. When people think of Tom Spargo, Spargo said, many would consider my reputation as a kind of partisan hack lawyer or Republican law expert. But when you get on the bench, then all that is behind you.... [F]rankly, I have not had a political thought in any of the work that Ive done as a judge. It was one thing to acknowledge that politics played a part in judicial life, but it was altogether something else to argue that judicial decisionmaking was all politics. When it came to legal realism, Spargo seemed to suggest, it was best to accept a little bit, but not too much.

Spargos ambivalent reaction to his own exoneration seemed hard to believe. How could he consistently lay claim to the roles of both politician and judge? He had assiduously courted voters through frankly political electioneering. On the basis of his behavior, one could easily infer that Spargo was a judge who could be counted on to represent the interests of his political supporters. Yet, if this were true, then Spargo had misled litigants and the general public by claiming to be unbiased. By trying to have it both ways, simultaneously playing partisan politics and claiming judicial impartiality, Spargo risked looking like a hypocrite: his courtroom behavior appeared to be an act, an effort to affect a degree of neutrality and open-mindedness which he did not possess. He claimed to give litigants a serious hearing, but his behavior suggested that he was just giving them the pretense of being heard .

In principle, Spargo easily could have avoided landing in such a bind. He could have stuck to a single role and thus eliminated the appearance of hypocrisy. For example, he could have responded to his courtroom victory by insisting that judicial decisionmaking is a thoroughly political enterprise. The goal, Spargo might have claimed, is not to pretend that judges operate on the basis of neutral legal principles but to recognize that judges are political actors with power over controversial policy questions. As a result, Spargo could have argued that open judicial politicking is a welcome sight. Vigorous judicial elections contested by aggressively political candidates allow voters to select and control the officials responsible for making legal policy. Reasoning along such lines, Spargo might have sincerely defended his actions as a critical contribution to democratic politics.

Alternatively, Spargo could have denounced the claims of legal realism from the outset. He could have argued that although elected politicians are necessarily obligated to represent the voters who placed them in office, judges are only required to represent the Law. The job of the judge, Spargo might have claimed, is to reason strictly on the basis of legal principle, to assimilate each dispute before the court into a coherent legal order, and to articulate a framework of rules capable of regulating subsequent judicial decisions. Spargo could have run a low-key, nonpartisan campaign and muted his political participation once on the bench. Indeed, he could have argued against the whole idea of judicial elections and insisted that a judges loyalty to the law rightly renders him indifferent to popularity. Had Spargo sincerely cultivated a reputation for independence and impartiality, he would have eliminated the risk of being seen as a partisan hack lawyer. He would have had no reason to contest charges leveled by the Commission on Judicial Conduct, since he would have never engaged in any judicially untoward actions in the first place.

And yet Spargo did not adopt either of these alternative strategies. Instead of choosing between the roles of active politician and impartial judge, he clung to both and defended his behavior by arguing that judges are political actorsexcept when they are not.

The legal realism that Spargo at once embraced and renounced has a venerable lineage. In 1897, Oliver Wendell Holmes, then a member of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts, warned his Boston University School of Law audience against supposing that the only force at work in the development of the law is logic. This mode of thinking is entirely natural, Holmes admitted. The training of lawyers is the training in logic. The processes of analogy, discrimination, and deduction are those in which they are most at home. The language of judicial decision is mainly the language of logic. And logical method and form flatter that longing for certainty and repose which is in every mind. The natural mode of thinking about the law clearly feels right, but Holmes argued that it is in fact wrong. Certainty, Holmes famously said, is illusion and repose is not the destiny of man. Behind the logical form lies a judgment as to the relative worth of and importance of competing legislative grounds, often an inarticulate and unconscious judgment, it is true, and yet the very root and nerve of the whole proceeding. Lawyers and judges may talk of sound logic, impersonal principle, and impartial judgment, but the law is actually driven by politics.

In the decades following Holmess address, a loose group of scholars that came to be known as legal realists took up Holmess remarks and fashioned them into a way of thinking about the judicial process. The realists devoted themselves to exposing the role played by politics in judicial decisionmaking and, in doing so, they called into question conventional efforts to anchor judicial power on a fixed legal foundation. The realist rejection of objective judicial reasoning proved to be quite popular and has been widely adopted. Less than one hundred years after Holmes spoke, a prominent legal historian noted that the claim we are all realists now had been made so often in legal scholarship that it was a kind of truism.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law»

Look at similar books to All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law»

Discussion, reviews of the book All Judges Are Political—Except When They Are Not: Acceptable Hypocrisies and the Rule of Law and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.