• Complain

Bruce Gordon - The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science

Here you can read online Bruce Gordon - The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2014, publisher: Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ORD), genre: Religion. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Bruce Gordon The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science
  • Book:
    The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ORD)
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2014
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

The intellectual and cultural battles now raging over theism and atheism, conservatism and secular progressivism, dualism and monism, realism and antirealism, and transcendent reality versus material reality extend even into the scientific disciplines. This stunning new volume captures this titanic clash of worldviews among those who have thought most deeply about the nature of science and of the universe itself. Unmatched in its breadth and scope, The Nature of Nature brings together some of the most influential scientists, scholars, and public intellectuals-including three Nobel laureates-across a wide spectrum of disciplines and schools of thought. Here they grapple with a perennial question that has been made all the more pressing by recent advances in the natural sciences: Is the fundamental explanatory principle of the universe, life, and self-conscious awareness to be found in inanimate matter or immaterial mind? The answers found in this book have profound implications for what it means to do science, what it means to be human, and what the future holds for all of us.

Bruce Gordon: author's other books


Who wrote The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

T HE N ATURE OF N ATURE

Examining the Role of
Naturalism in Science

Edited by
Bruce L. Gordon
and William A. Dembski

The Nature of Nature Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science - image 1

Wilmington , Delaware

C ONTENTS

Steve Fuller

Bruce L. Gordon and William A. Dembski

PART I:
NATURALIZING SCIENCE:
SOME HISTORICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL CONSIDERATIONS

Bruce L. Gordon

Ronald L. Numbers

Ernan McMullin

Stephen C. Meyer

PART II:
THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL AND ONTOLOGICAL
FOUNDATIONS OF NATURALISM

Alvin C. Plantinga

William J. Talbott

A. Its No Illusion! Alvin C. Plantinga

B. The End of an Illusion? William J. Talbott

Bruce L. Gordon

Robert C. Koons

Alvin I. Goldman

Michael Williams

Nicholas Wolterstorff

PART III:
THE ORIGIN OF BIOLOGICAL INFORMATION AND THE
EMERGENCE OF BIOLOGICAL COMPLEXITY

David Berlinski

Stephen C. Meyer

Christian de Duve

William A. Dembski and Robert J. Marks II

Mark Ptashne

Douglas D. Axe

Michael J. Behe

Michael Shermer

Fazale R. Rana

PART IV:
COSMOLOGICAL ORIGINS AND FINE-TUNING

Alan Guth

William Lane Craig

Howard J. Van Till

Steven Weinberg

Bruce L. Gordon

Guillermo Gonzalez

PART V:
MATHEMATICS

Philip Kitcher

Mark Steiner

PART VI:
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, NEUROSCIENCE,
AND CONSCIOUSNESS

John Tooby and Leda Cosmides

David Berlinski

John R. Searle

Francis Crick and Christof Koch

Nancey Murphy

Stuart Hameroff and Roger Penrose

Henry P. Stapp

James P. Moreland

PART VII: SCIENCE, ETHICS, AND RELIGION

Michael Ruse

Dallas Willard

Michael Tooley

William Lane Craig

F OREWORD

B EYOND N ATURALISM TO S CIENCE

S TEVE F ULLER

I can appreciate a book called The Nature of Nature because I have called myself a reflexive naturalist. If naturalism is the default metaphysical position of the natural sciences, then that fact must itself be explained by the theories and methods of the natural sciences. But how does one do that without begging crucial questions? For example, it is tempting to argue that the natural sciences are simply a somewhat more disciplined version of commonsense, which itself is an extension of the problem-solving skills that all animals deploy in adapting to their environments. Such a view was explicitly promoted in the twentieth century by the American pragmatists John Dewey and Willard Quine, both of whom invoked naturalism to name their own positions. It had the virtue of bringing science down to earth by making it seem to be part of our evolutionary heritage. But in the process, this view presumed that the natural sciences ideological self-understanding was largely correct. In other words, science was explained as an instance of something of which it was already trying to provide a theoretical account. Yet the epistemic distinctiveness of science, whereby it breaks with animal modes of intelligence and even everyday forms of human reasoning, remained unaddressed, if not obscured, in the process.

If science were indeed little more than incrementally enhanced ordinary perceptionsay, the indefinite aggregation of beings with indefinitely powerful eyesthen the history of science would not have been as it is. Long before Thomas Kuhn, it was recognized that science periodically reconstitutes societys taken-for-granted ideas, regardless of whether that serves to stabilize or destabilize our place in nature. For example, the relativity and quantum revolutions in twentieth-century physics shifted sciences epistemic center of gravity very far from commonsense and in ways that have placed humanitys survival increasingly at risk. Notwithstanding a persistent undercurrent of protest, sometimes in the name of humanity but increasingly in the name of nature, we have acted as if the benefits of science outweigh the costs. But what is the source of this overriding faith? After all, the practical benefits continue to be controversialas in, say, nuclear energy, stem-cell research, and nanotechnology.

Nevertheless, sciences theoretical benefits remain clear. In particular, the revolutions in physics appear unequivocally good because they significantly advance the distinctly human quest for universal knowledge in at least three senses of that term, all of which cut against the spirit of naturalism:

(1) Science aspires to knowledge of all things, under conditions potential and actual, regardless of their relevance to our everyday lives, let alone personal or species survival. Indeed, most of what science purports to be about will never be experienced directly by anyone, and only a very small fraction of the reality charted by science will be encountered even by expert scientists. Another, more empowering way to make the same point is to say that what we may come to know is not restricted to what we have known. In that sense, science transcends history. A scientific inquiry into the nature of life or the nature of mind may begin by examining living organisms and conscious humans, but it then poses the question in broader, more abstract terms, countenancing the range of material properties that living and conscious beings might possess, wherever they might be.

(2) Science aspires to articulate all things in a common language, no matter how different these things may appear to our senses. Newton first achieved this feat by mathematically unifying our understanding of the motions of the planets and objects on Earth. John Locke, one of the original Newtonians, canonized the difference between how things are and how they seem to be in terms of primary and secondary qualities. In the wake of Newton, mathematics quest to articulate the primary qualities of things has led the discipline to develop in directions far removed from ordinary tasks of measurement and calculation, from non-Euclidean geometries to the paradoxes of set theory. Corresponding to that has been the introduction of specialized uses for ordinary terms as well as some entirely new terms and conceptualizations that have periodically challenged our basic understanding of space, time, and cause. In this context, for better or worse, symbolic logic has been promoted as the language of universal thought.

(3) Science aspires to be knowledge for everyone, a universal human legacy. This is the sense in which science most controversially defies naturalism. The palpable diversity of human beingsbe it by origins or appearanceis not sufficient to discount their experience and ideas from the constitution of scientific knowledge. On the contrary, a mark of the unscientific standing of a form of knowledge is that it cannot command universal human assent by virtue of its intimate connection to personal experience. Of course, this is not to deny that different people understand things differently. Rather, it is to say that for such an understanding to count as science, it must be made relevant to those who have not and probably will not experience it for themselves. The principle applies equally to someone possessing arcane technical expertise and rare indigenous knowledge. Here the positivist philosophical distinction between the context of discovery and the context of justification is apt: The more widely justifiable a form of knowledge is, the greater its entitlement to scientific status.

All three senses of sciences universality defy any easy naturalistic explanation because they force us to conceptualize knowledge from a standpoint rather removed from our ordinary embodied experience. Thomas Nagel famously identified this standpoint as the view from nowhere, which certainly captures the spirit of points (1) and (2) above. But in fact science requires what Laudan called aristocratic induction, that is, the ability to see beyond our default expectations to something deeper and even counterintuitive. This point applies to how we regard not only the natural world but also those who regard the natural world.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science»

Look at similar books to The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science»

Discussion, reviews of the book The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.