• Complain

Philip Clayton - The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith

Here you can read online Philip Clayton - The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2011, publisher: Oxford University Press, genre: Religion. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover
  • Book:
    The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Oxford University Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2011
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Does it make sense - can it make sense - for someone who appreciates the explanatory power of modern science to continue believing in a traditional religious account of the ultimate nature and purpose of our universe? This book is intended for those who care about that question and are dissatisfied with the rigid dichotomies that dominate the contemporary debate. The extremists wont be interested - those who assume that science answers all the questions that matter, and those so certain of their religious faith that dialogue with science, philosophy, or other faith traditions seems unnecessary. But far more people today recognize that matters of faith are complex, that doubt is endemic to belief, and that dialogue is indispensable in our day.
In eight probing chapters, the authors of The Predicament of Belief consider the most urgent reasons for doubting that religious claims - in particular, those embedded in the Christian tradition - are likely to be true. They develop a version of Christian faith that preserves the traditions core insights but also gauges the varying degrees of certainty with which those insights can still be affirmed. Along the way, they address such questions as the ultimate origin of the universe, the existence of innocent suffering, the challenge of religious plurality, and how to understand the extraordinary claim that an ancient teacher rose from the dead. They end with a discussion of what their conclusions imply about the present state and future structure of churches and other communities in which Christian affirmations are made.

Philip Clayton: author's other books


Who wrote The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Contents
(p.vii) Preface

This is a difficult era for those who find themselves committed to the values of scientific rationality and yet moved by the claims of a religious tradition. It is rare for such persons to receive a hearing, let alone an enthusiastic one, from either the scientifically minded or the religiously committed. Formerly open camps have circled the wagons, and exploratory dialogue has given way to ad hominem rhetoric. Not surprisingly in such a climate, it is not easy for inquiring readers to find resources that will help them determine how far the assumptions of science, together with other sources of religious doubt, really do cut into the viability of religious claims. As a result, it is hard to decide what parts of ones tradition it makes sense to reject or retain.

To look with probing, even skeptical eyes at religious belief is not, after all, a normal part of the work of religious scholars, at least not in our day. In an era of increasingly open hostility toward religious truth claims, some of it voiced by distinguished scientists, it has become almost exclusively the task of secular philosophers and other opponents of religion to raise the probing questions. In response, religious scholars are inclined more and more to take a defensive posture, focusing their efforts on protecting religion in general, or more often the specific beliefs of their own tradition, from attack. In an era of such antipathy toward religious truth claimsso the reasoning appears to goscholars who are in any way sympathetic to religion should concentrate exclusively on its defense, lest they inadvertently give ammunition to its opponents.

As understandable as this response may be, it has produced a literature unhelpfully confined to rhetorical combat. Those who eschew both sides have usually become agnostics, abjuring the debate in favor of spiritual practices, religious ethics, or a mystical unknowing in the face of questions of ultimacy. Best-seller lists are packed with hostile treatments of religious belief bearing titles such as The God Delusion, (p.viii) God is Not Great, Breaking the Spell, and Religion Explained; they in turn have spawned dozens of religious counterattacks. But remarkably rare are the treatments that, while basically sympathetic to religious belief, attempt to sift carefully through the arguments for and against core religious propositions such as the existence of God. Precisely this lack in the contemporary literature provides the motivation of this book.

Now there might seem to be a glaring error in the claim just made. Is the market not full of books that criticize religious traditions from within and advocate revising them in ways that will make them more relevant to the world we now live in? Such books have subjected Christian, Jewish, and, more recently, Muslim belief and practice to piercing scrutiny. They typically argue that much (and many argue that virtually all) of what these traditions once held is no longer plausible. At first glance, it would seem that these books sufficiently fill the need for self-critical treatments of religious belief.

As a rule, however, the revisionists perform only half the required task. Among those interested in the Christian tradition, for example, the revisionist or liberal authors are frankly critical of inherited doctrines, cheerfully jettisoning convictions that once defined the core commitments of Christianity. And yet many authors subject their own proposals to rather less critical attention (although there are some notable exceptions). Whatever is deemed worthy of preservingan experience of new being, a commitment to environmental stewardship, or resistance to racial, sexual, or economic oppressionis often put forward with the same unwavering passion of religious conviction with which the traditional beliefs themselves were once advanced. More to the immediate point: less critical scrutiny is focused on the assumptions that lead these authors to reject the religious truth claims their own proposals are intended to replace.

In all the respects we have just mentioned, commentary on religion typically stops short, at present, of addressing what we are calling the predicament of religious belief in todays world. That predicament, as we understand it, has two facets: on one side, the difficulty of formulating traditional claims about what is ultimately the case in ways that take full account of all the reasons for doubting those claims; on the other side, the need to do justice to the axiological and theoretical power of those accounts of ultimate reality that metaphysical reflection and religious traditions variously suggest.

represent, in our judgment, deep and serious challenges. These are the kinds of worries that give or should give serious pause to people who are wondering whether Christian beliefthe case on which we will mainly focusis still viable. Moreover, it seems to us that theologians who work professionally at formulating religious teachings have an obligation to understand and respond to these grounds for doubt. It may well be the case that belief in God, at least in its Christian form, should not continue unchanged in the face of these critical concerns.

Yet we are not convinced that these worries by themselves are sufficient to render every belief in some form of ultimate reality outdated or irrational. Over the course of a research program lasting more than two decades now, in numerous conference publications, and in a variety of articles and books, we have sought to determine what revisions were required by the challenges to belief and what responses remained available in the face of those challenges. When it comes to the more specific claims of the Christian tradition, one must acknowledge the specific assumptions, commitments, and experiences that motivate an ongoing interest in this tradition and its particular affirmations. Given this set of interests, we will show, some traditional claims remain problematic, some have an indeterminate status, and some are in fact untouched by the standard criticisms. Even in the case of Christianitys most contentious claims, those regarding the ultimate fate and status of its founder, it turns out that there is a relatively small number of serious objections and a limited number of ways of responding to them. When one gives these matters sustained critical attention, resisting the tendency toward snap judgments in one direction or another, it is possible to develop a pretty good sense of the lay of the land.

We are under no illusion, however, that the arguments presented in this book are likely to sway those in either of the warring camps mentioned at the outset. There is no way, for instance, to compel a physicist who regards the universe as simply the meaningless result of mindless forces to take seriouslyor to regard with any interest at allthe degree to which the very ability of human beings to understand (p.x) such phenomena raises questions that point beyond what physics itself can establish. We cannot deny the immense emotional appeal of restricting ones view of reality to whatever can be measured and explained by the lights of ones own discipline! Similarly, there is no way to compel a contented believer in traditional religious claims to take seriously the grounds for wondering if those claims are actually true. Our arguments are not aimed at those who are happy to remain at either extreme, but are offered as guidance for those who wish to go where reason and experience may lead. We dedicate this effort to all, of every faith or no faith, who approach the ultimate reality in that spirit.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith»

Look at similar books to The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith»

Discussion, reviews of the book The Predicament of Belief: Science, Philosophy, and Faith and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.