• Complain

Pierre Manent - Natural Law and Human Rights

Here you can read online Pierre Manent - Natural Law and Human Rights full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2020, publisher: University of Notre Dame Press, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Pierre Manent Natural Law and Human Rights
  • Book:
    Natural Law and Human Rights
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    University of Notre Dame Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2020
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Natural Law and Human Rights: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Natural Law and Human Rights" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Pierre Manent is one of Frances leading political philosophers. This first English translation of his profound and strikingly original book La loi naturelle et les droits de lhomme is a reflection on the central question of the Western political tradition. In six chapters, developed from the prestigious tienne Gilson lectures at the Institut Catholique de Paris, and in a related appendix, Manent contemplates the steady displacement of the natural law by the modern conception of human rights. He aims to restore the grammar of moral and political action, and thus the possibility of an authentically political order that is fully compatible with liberty rightly understood.Manent boldly confronts the prejudices and dogmas of those who have repudiated the classical and (especially) Christian notion of liberty under law and in the process shows how groundless many contemporary appeals to human rights turn out to be. Manent denies that we can generate obligations from a condition of what Locke, Hobbes, and Rousseau call the state of nature, where human beings are absolutely free, with no obligations to others. In his view, our ever-more-imperial affirmation of human rights needs to be reintegrated into what he calls an archic understanding of human and political existence, where law and obligation are inherent in liberty and meaningful human action. Otherwise we are bound to act thoughtlessly in an increasingly arbitrary or willful manner.Natural Law and Human Rights will engage students and scholars of politics, philosophy, and religion, and will captivate sophisticated readers who are interested in the question of how we might reconfigure our knowledge of, and talk with one another about, politics.

Pierre Manent: author's other books


Who wrote Natural Law and Human Rights? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Natural Law and Human Rights — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Natural Law and Human Rights" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Landmarks
Page-list

Appendix

Recovering Laws Intelligence

Each eras agony receives its physiognomy from a certain tangle of problems, from a specific difficulty in responding to the primary human question: What is to be done? This difficulty is inseparably practical and theoretical; it concerns inseparably action and intelligence. Since human action is in the first instance corrective or rectifying, it presupposes as precise a diagnosis as possible of our situation as calling for a remedy, a diagnosis of our predicamentto take back an old French word that the English took from us, as is their habit. What then is our predicament?

I believe that the most precise way to designate what afflicts us, what troubles and demoralizes us, is to say simply: we no longer know what law is; we have lost the intelligence of law. The point is not to deplore that we disobey the law, that our morals are disordered, that the youth, as is often said, are without standardsall that is perhaps true, but the main point is that we no longer understand what the law is about. We no longer understand law according to its essence. We no longer understand law as the rule and measure of action. Our most urgent task is therefore to recover the intelligence of law as rule and measure of action. Thomas Aquinas is certainly the author who can best help usChristians as well as non-Christians confronted with the loss of laws meaningto carry out this task, if only we make the effort to understand his work in its full amplitude. The purpose of this presentation is nevertheless not so much to expound Thomass restorative views as to examine our predicament more closely.

I have said that we have lost an understanding of law, or laws intelligence. We have not lost it by inadvertence or negligence. We have lost it because we wanted to lose it. More precisely, we have fled from law. We are still fleeing from it. We have been fleeing from law since we took up the projectlet us call it the modern projectto organize common life, the human world, on a basis other than law. We have been fleeing from the law since we undertook to regulate our actions otherwise than by law, to seek the rule of our actions elsewhere than in law. This is not a matter of a moments distraction or mistake. What is at stake is an immense enterprise to which we owe, for better and for worse, the driving and ordering of our common life over three or four centuries.

The adequate description of this enterprise cannot be my subject here. I shall limit myself to the indispensable points. If our actions are not to be regulated by law, then what shall regulate them? What kind of rule can replace law? We know that for a long time we have intended to regulate common life not according to Gods or natures law but according to human rights. Man is the being who possesses rights, and to live humanly is to assert ones rights. This new definition or determination is not sufficient. It still retains something negative or polemical: to assert ones rights is to defend them against those who deprive you of your rights, who harm or violate them, or against a society that is always curtailing them. In order to be able to order collective life completely or sufficiently, another, positive principle is needed, that of self-interest. The person who asserts his or her rights is also one who seeks his or her interests. Rights and self-interest are the two principles that allow for the ordering of the human world without recourse to law as the rule and measure of action. Of course we still have laws, indeed more laws than ever, but their raison dtre is no longer directly to regulate our actions but rather to guarantee our rights and equip us to seek our interests in a way that is useful or at least not harmful to the common interest. The sovereign, liberal, and representative state, by guaranteeing our rights, protects and encourages civil society, which is the framework within which we freely seek our interests. This is our political formula.

This immense political enterprise produces and presupposes a profound transformation of our humanity, as social beings and citizens. The person who asserts his rights and seeks his self-interest is no longer the agent for whom law provides the rule and measure of action. As the being who has rights and pursues his interests, he defines himself first of all in relation to himself, a relation that is subjective or subjectifying and by which he guarantees his independence with regard to any objective rule, that is, any law of God or of nature. This back and forth between self and self, this circle of self to self, verifies that the human being bears within his being no objective rule of action. In this sense the movement of subjectification according to rights and interests leads to the dismantling of the edifice of conscience or the preempting of its construction. The habitus that contains the principles of natural law must be deprived of force or validity in order to allow the subject fully to assert its right and its interest in the face of the right and interest of other subjects. The rule of action no longer resides within the agent but outside of subjects, at the interface where subjects meet each other. This strange exchange by which the subject deprives himself of the sure law that resided in his being, in his conscience, in order to go off in search of an indeterminate and unstable rule in the encounter with similarly disarmed subjects, this search for the self through the effacement of what gives the self its integrity, would merit a long examination, at once historical and systematic. Here we will limit ourselves to the consequences of this transformation of the agent into the subject.

These consequences range from the intimate to the immense: they affect what is most delicate for every human being as well as the whole of humanity in the way that it orders itself as a mass.

The immense refers to the world. Agents fleeing law have become subjects regulating their actions according to the world. Rejecting or leaving behind the laws of God or of naturereligious, moral, and political law that once regulated and measured their actions by making agents participants in a community, whether church, political body, or familysubjects have tended more and more to assert their rights and to pursue their interests in the unlimited space of the world by forming an immense system of action that has gained an authority over us that is without rival, under the name of the global market. The rule that the law no longer gives us, or that we no longer want to receive from the law, we seek very precisely at the end of the world, in these commandments that are sent back our way, with a power that subjugates the will and dumbfounds thought, by the world as the totality of human beings as rendered effective by the market or by markets. These are recent developments, but they were, as it were, contained in the Cartesian project of making us like masters and possessors of nature. What is striking in this project is that it proposed an immense horizon of action, which opened up an unlimited career for this project, without attaching any rule or measure to it. Today the project has come up against its limit. We ask ourselves anxiously how to protect nature against its master and possessor; we seek in nature itself the law of our lawlessness. If what we have said up to this point has any pertinence, this question will remain vain. This is not to say that it is not necessary to preserve nature as much as possible, but the idea of protection in itself bears no rule of action any more than does the idea of the mastery of nature. We will effectively protect nature only if we rediscover the rule of human action, that is, law.

As I have said, the consequences of the transformation of the agent into the subject affect not only the immense but also the intimate. Since the subject flees law as such, there can be no rule for regulating the association in which the human being unites himself to another human being to found a unit capable of producing a new human being and thus continuing humanity. One of the most essential laws is that which, as it were, holds together the difference of the sexes with the difference of generations. The other sex is the strange proximity of that which is furthest away; the other generation is the strange distance of what is nearest. No human being can by himself regulate this distance or this proximity. To try to do so is to enter into a vertigo, a loss of the self from which there is no return. This is why laws of marriage and of filiation in a way make up the original laws of the human world. We have undertaken to abolish them in order to put in their place the freedom of invention and artifice of a subject defined in relation to his or her desire. In the place of the law that builds a bridge or sews a seam between the primary constituents of the human world, we put the project of a subject that means to remain in an infinite proximity with itself and thus to fabricate bonds at its pleasure. We often wonder today how homosexual activism was able to determine to such a degree the terms of the public debate, even though its legal claims are really and sincerely shared by a very small part of society. Homosexual desire places the relation to self in a position of inviolable sovereignty, since it cannot give place either to the natural difference of sexes or the natural difference of generations. By completely legalizing homosexual unions, we have achieved or intended to achieve a human world as detached from law as from nature, detached from natural law in the strongest and most pregnant sense of this expression. Homosexual desire, as desire, cares nothing for law. By nevertheless demanding to be legalized, it invalidates and abrogates law as such, law as the rule and measure of action. This is not true in the case of the law of heterosexual marriage, which is not primarily about heterosexual desire, but about the sexual difference. The legalization of homosexual marriage provides the modern project with something like its final destination, the proof that we have succeeded in organizing the human world without rule or measure, that we are finally living, and know that we are living, outside the law.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Natural Law and Human Rights»

Look at similar books to Natural Law and Human Rights. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Natural Law and Human Rights»

Discussion, reviews of the book Natural Law and Human Rights and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.