• Complain

Marc Gasser-Wingate - Aristotles Empiricism

Here you can read online Marc Gasser-Wingate - Aristotles Empiricism full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2021, publisher: Oxford University Press, genre: Science. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Marc Gasser-Wingate Aristotles Empiricism
  • Book:
    Aristotles Empiricism
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Oxford University Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2021
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Aristotles Empiricism: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Aristotles Empiricism" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Aristotle is famous for thinking that all our knowledge comes from perception. But its not immediately clear what this view is meant to entail. Its not clear, for instance, what perception is supposed to contribute to the more advanced forms of knowledge that derive from it. Nor is it clear
how we should understand the nature of its contribution--what it might mean to say that these more advanced forms of knowledge are derived from or based on what we perceive.

Aristotle is often thought to have disappointingly little to say on these matters. Gasser-Wingate makes the case that this thought is mistaken: a coherent and philosophically attractive view of perceptual knowledge can be found in the various texts in which Aristotle discusses perceptions role in
animal life, the cognitive resources on which it does and does not depend, and the relation it bears to practical and theoretical modes of understanding.

Aristotles Empiricism offers a sustained examination of these discussions and their epistemological, psychological, and ethical implications. It defends an interpretation of Aristotle as a moderate sort of empiricist, who thinks we can develop sophisticated forms of knowledge by broadly perceptual
means--and that we therefore share an important part of our cognitive lives with nonrational animals--but also holds that our intellectual powers allow us to surpass these animals in certain ways and thereby develop distinctively human forms of understanding.

Marc Gasser-Wingate: author's other books


Who wrote Aristotles Empiricism? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Aristotles Empiricism — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Aristotles Empiricism" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Aristotles Empiricism - image 1
Aristotles Empiricism

Aristotles Empiricism - image 2

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the Universitys objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries.

Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press

198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.

Oxford University Press 2021

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above.

You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.

Library of Congress Control Number: 2021932106

ISBN 9780197567456

eISBN 9780197567470

DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197567487.001.0001

Acknowledgments

The questions animating this project are ones I became interested in while working on my doctoral thesis at Harvard. I am deeply grateful to my advisors, Mary Louise Gill, Rusty Jones, Alison Simmons, and Gisela Striker, for their comments and guidance during those years.

Papers discussing various arguments developed in the book were presented at conferences and workshops at Brown University, Dart-mouth College, Harvard University, Northwestern University, the University of Pennsylvania, Providence College, the University of Sheffield, Temple University, the University of Toronto, and at the 2018 Eastern APA, the 2018 SAGP Annual Meeting, the 2018 Boston Summer Workshop, the Tahoe Ancient Philosophy Workshop, and the Orange Beach Epistemology Workshop. I am thankful to the audiences at these events for their criticism and feedback. Thanks are also due to my wonderful colleagues at Boston University, who generously commented on early, unpolished drafts of this material; to the Boston University Center for the Humanities, whose Junior Faculty Fellowship provided me with a critical semester of research leave; and to the CABAL and its associates for the supportive and stimulating philosophical community they help create. As Aristotle reminds us, we can all do philosophy alone, but we do it better with friends.

For helpful discussions about the central ideas developed in this book, I thank: David Charles, Sukaina Hirji, Robert Howton, Dhananjay Jagannathan, Colin King, Emily Kress, Jim Lennox, Hendrik Lorenz, Keith McPartland, Katy Meadows, Benjamin Morison, Jessica Moss, Christiana Olfert, Evan Rodriguez, David Roochnik, Susan Sauv Meyer, and Jacob Stump. I also wish to thank Katja Vogt and an anonymous reader for Oxford University Press, who provided very detailed and careful comments on every part of the manuscript. The book owes much to their efforts. Finally, I am especially thankful to David Bronstein, whose thoughtful and always generous comments greatly improved the central arguments in the book; to Doug Kremm, for his steady philosophical spirit and for always being a willing interlocutor; to Patricia Marechal, for countless, invariably helpful conversations about nearly every aspect of the book; and to Whitney Schwab, for looking at early chapter drafts and keeping me honest during research leave.

Some parts of on behalf of BSHP. I wish to thank these presses for permitting the inclusion of the relevant materials. I also wish to thank Peter Ohlin, my editor at Oxford University Press, for his sound advice and his interest in this project, and Zara Amdur, for her help compiling the books index. Any errors are of course my own responsibility.

Above all I thank my partner, Amanda, for her patient, loving, and insightful support. I owe her more than I can express.

Contents

Aristotle is famous for thinking that all our knowledge comes from perception. Of course, we acquire knowledge in many different ways we learn from our teachers, parents, colleagues, and friends, or from accumulated personal experience, or through various forms of reasoning, or indeed out of mere force of habit. But all these forms of learning, Aristotle thinks, rest on some sort of prior knowledgethe knowledge of our teachers, say, or of the premises in our arguments, or of our own past experiences. And generally this prior knowledge will itself depend on further prior knowledge. Where does the regress end With perceptual knowledgethe only sort of knowledge that is not itself derived from anything prior. Perception is thus supposed to provide a bedrock for our learning, by supplying us with knowledge in a way that doesnt depend on our already having some knowledge at our disposal.

This view of our cognitive beginnings plays a central role in Aristotles epistemology. Hes sometimes considered the first empiricist for having held it. But its not immediately clear what the view is meant to entail. Its not clear, for instance, what the knowledge perception supplies would contribute to the more advanced states that Aristotle takes to derive from itstates like experience (), craft knowledge (), or scientific understanding (). Nor is it clear how we should understand the nature of its contribution what it might mean for various forms of knowledge to be based on or derived from perceptual knowledge. Indeed, to some ears it will already sound puzzling that there could be such a thing as perceptual knowledge, or that any form of knowledge would emerge directly from perception, without any sort of inference, or any (perhaps implicit) reliance on our existing beliefs or conceptual resources. My aim in this book is to shed some light on these questions: to give an account of the sort of empiricism Aristotle espoused, and of his broader conception of perceptions place in our cognitive lives.

Of course empiricism is a slippery label. To say that all our knowledge issues from perception is not yet to say that perception itself plays a more than incidental role in our learning. Platos middle dialogues provide a good illustration of this point: perception is presented as a necessary starting point for our learning because it prompts a form of recollection that supplies us with expert knowledge. But perception isnt itself characterized as an epistemically valuable state: it prompts recollection by perplexing us, summoning thought and awakening the intellect into recovering knowledge already present in our souls, and which might serve to sort out what perception alone could not make clear. On this kind of view perception does serve as a starting point for all our learning, insofar as it occasions the rest of our cognitive development. But it doesnt provide an edifice for more advanced forms of knowledge, or supply the basic materials from which these forms of knowledge would be derived.

Even if perception did serve as some sort of edifice, one might wonder just how much it could teach us on its own. For Aristotle often emphasizes that our capacity to perceive is a capacity we share with all animals, and which yields a form of knowledge far removed from the sort of theoretical understanding he takes as his cognitive idealas he puts it in the Metaphysics, to perceive is common to all, and therefore easy, and nothing wise (A2 982a1112). In particular perception doesnt tell us

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Aristotles Empiricism»

Look at similar books to Aristotles Empiricism. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Aristotles Empiricism»

Discussion, reviews of the book Aristotles Empiricism and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.