• Complain

Leon Golden - Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy

Here you can read online Leon Golden - Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2017, publisher: Radius Book Group, genre: Science. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Leon Golden Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy
  • Book:
    Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Radius Book Group
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2017
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy is the latest of Leon Goldens books to connect Ancient Greece to modern culture. In a world facing many pressing issues Classics professor Golden wants to champion the values and achievements of Classical Civilization. He asserts that Homeric Epic and Greek Tragedy are as relevant today as they were millennia ago because they are riveting and insightful studies of the human condition. Their universality grants them a contemporary relevance despite the passage of time and changes in custom and taste.
In one of his previous books, Understanding the Iliad, Golden illuminated the relevance of The Iliad for modern readers. The Bryn Mawr Classical Review praised Understanding the Iliad because it, achieves what it sets out to accomplish: to provide an interpretation of the Iliad that emphasizes its didactic aspects, its ability to improve its readers by presenting the spectacle of the evolution of a flawed warrior consumed by destructive anger to a legitimate hero who transcends his narcissism and grandiosity and reaches out to others and by doing so heals his own aching soul in the process.
Golden, making use of correspondence and personal contact with Joseph Heller, himself, argues convincingly in Achilles and Yossarian that Homers The Iliad exerted a profound influence over Heller as he wrote his modern classic, Catch-22. A Kirkus review acclaims Achilles and Yossarian in these words: Golden combines impressive erudition with a sharp critical eye and a lucid prose style that laymen will find accessible and engaging. The result is an original and persuasive work of literary scholarship that finds much more than mere war stories in these classics.

Leon Golden: author's other books


Who wrote Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make


All mankind yearn by nature for knowledge.

Aristotle, Metaphysics 1.980

Table of Contents


The author gratefully acknowledges permission to use the following copyrighted content:

Martha C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy , 2nd Edition. Copyright 2001 Martha C. Nussbaum. Reprinted with the Additional: permission of Cambridge University Press.

Excerpt(s) from Death of a Salesman by Arthur Miller, copyright 1949, renewed 1977 by Arthur Miller. Used by permission of Viking Books, an imprint of Penguin Publishing Group, a division of Penguin Random House LLC. All rights reserved.

J. Gassner, Catharsis and the Modern Theater, in Aristotles Poetics and English Literature , ed. Elder Olson (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1965), 10813; essay originally published in One Act Play Magazine and Theater Review (August 1937). 1965 by The University of Chicago Press. All rights reserved. Published 1965. Printed in the United States of America. Used by permission of University of Chicago Press.

Aristotles Poetics: A Translation and Commentary for Students of Literature . Translated by Leon Golden and commentary by O. B. Hardison, Jr. Gainesville: University Press of Florida, 1982. Used by permission of University Press of Florida.

I.

All mankind yearn by nature for knowledge.

Aristotle, Metaphysics 1.980

The elegantly simple, impressively profound comment by Aristotle in his Metaphysics is, I propose, the necessary basis for understanding the essential argument of his influential treatise on poetic theory, the Poetics . This seminal work is still treated with scholarly reverence and cited as a doctrinal authority on matters literary. However, it is imperfectly or seriously misunderstood regarding one or more concepts of the greatest significance, which it places before us as instruments of interpretation.

Two causes appear to have brought poetry into existence and these are natural causes. For the process of mimesis is natural to mankind from childhood on and it is in this way that human beings differ from other animals, because they are the most imitative of them and achieve their first learning experiences through mimesis . A proof of this is what really happens; for there are some things which are painful to us when we see them but we take pleasure in viewing the most precise representations of them, for example, the forms of the most despised wild animals and of corpses. The reason for this is that the act of learning is not only most pleasant to philosophers but, in a similar way, to everyone else, only others share in this pleasure to a more limited degree. For it is because of this that we take pleasure when we see representations because it turns out that in our viewing of them we learn and infer what each thing is, for example that this is that ( Poetics, 1448 b 417).

Aristotles apparently enigmatic phrase that this is that is persuasively explained by Bywater as follows: Our pleasure in the contemplation of a picture or other work of imitative art is explained here to be the natural concomitant of an intellectual act, the discovery or recognition on our part of the meaning of the picture.

The essential core in witnessing all imitative representations is then for Aristotle a cognitive event, a learning experience. There are in addition other common elements that Aristotle has observed that specifically define over the long arc of representations of the tragic some permanent and unchanging aspects of the human condition. Reformulated time and time again, these elements accurately define the role Aristotelian tragedy plays in human experience. Let us begin with that central figure often designated as the tragic hero, who is the principal agent in the operation of the tragic action. Aristotle defines the tragic hero as follows:

There remains the person whose character lies in between those who are of exceptional virtue and those who are afflicted with very great evil. Such a person is neither preeminent in virtue nor falls into misfortune because of vice and depravity. But rather because of some hamartia .... It is necessary for the good plot to have a single rather than a double ending, as some people say, and for the change of fortune to take place, not to good fortune from bad fortune, but just the opposite, from good to bad fortune, and not because of depravity but because of some significant hamartia on the part of such a person who has been described or on the part of a better rather than a worse one ( Poetics 1453 a 717).

For Aristotle, then, the center of our attention in the unfolding of the mimetic examination of tragic experience is a very specific kind of human being, one whose involvement in tragic circumstances is caused by a very specific kind of failing, a hamartia (Gk. ). Exactly what this critical term designates has been much discussed and variously interpreted whenever tragedy as a genre has appeared on the scene. But my argument in this treatise will be that any tragedy that authentically earns the designation of an Aristotelian tragedy requires that this term be understood in one specific way as described below by Gregory Crane:

An example from the study of ancient Greek attitudes illustrates the problems of linguistic interpretation. Aristotle, in the Poetics (1453 a 10), writes that the hero in a tragedy suffers disaster because of a hamartia. For at least 500 years, hamartia was understood as a moral error and gradually became crystallized as the tragic flaw of character. This interpretation cannot be maintained in the light of what Aristotle elsewhere says about hamartia (Lucas 1968: 299307), for he clearly uses this term as miscalculation or failure of judgment without moral implications of any kind, but because the Greek term hamartia was understood to designate a moral failing and because most scholars through the early 20th century expected classical texts to reinforce Christian ethics, this reading was not seriously challenged. The interpretation of a single word stood as the cornerstone for a complex reading of Greek (and other tragedy). Sophocles Oedipus Rex became trivialized into an unambiguous morality play wherein the proud and irascible Oedipus, deceived by the fatal flaw of pride, meets the fate that he richly deserves.

Crane here gives a succinct and persuasive justification why the all-too-common attempt to find a moral failure, a tragic flaw in the Oedipus Tyrannus specifically (but also in certain other tragedies) is itself a flawed enterprise.

Bywater had pointed out much earlier that:

hamartia in the Aristotelian sense of the term is a mistake or error of judgement and the deed done in consequence of it is a harmatema. In the Ethics an harmatema is said to originate not in vice or depravity but in ignorance of some material fact or circumstance. This ignorance we are told in another passage takes the deed out of the class of voluntary acts and enables one to forgive or even pity the doer.... It is strange that the hamartia ... of which Aristotle is speaking should have been taken... by others to mean not an error of judgment, but some ethical fault or infirmity of character.... The Sophoclean Oedipus is a man of hasty temper but his hamartia was not in that, but in the great mistake he made when he became unwittingly the slayer of his own father.

D. W. Lucas confirms the above interpretations of hamartia when he writes, This flaw or frailty is a popular starting point for the discussion of not only Greek Plays. But though hamartia can mean many things, there are few, if any, passages where flaw is a justifiable rendering and there can be little doubt that what A. recommends is a character neither very good nor very bad who makes a mistake.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy»

Look at similar books to Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy»

Discussion, reviews of the book Aristotle and the Arc of Tragedy and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.