• Complain

F. Russell Sullivan Jr. - Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard

Here you can read online F. Russell Sullivan Jr. - Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2009, publisher: UPA, genre: Science. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover
  • Book:
    Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    UPA
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2009
  • Rating:
    5 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 100
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

In this work, Sullivan analyzes the relationship between faith and reason in Kierkegaards philosophy. Kierkegaard is widely considered to be an irrationalist. Sullivan argues that he views faith as reasonable in a distinct way that must be uncovered. In some of his pseudonymous works, Kierkegaard speaks of the movement of faith as paradoxical and absurd. There is evidence from his non-pseudonymous works that Kierkgaard does not consider faith irrational. He denigrates reason only in that he wishes to impress upon nominal Christians (who look upon faith only as a body of doctrine) that more and more understanding of the tenets of faith can never yield logical certainty. The doctrines of faith can be argued pro and contra. For Kierkgaard, faith in this context is illogical, but not irrational. In his religious works, Kierkgaards notion of reason is inextricably tied in with that of his recalcitrance of the will. Reason (logic and speculative thought) attests to its own limits in regard to doctrinal faith, but it also can point to that which is a reasonable step, even when logic alone is of no avail. For Kierkgaard, subjectivity is a necessary - but not sufficient - condition of religious faith. In actuality, Kierkgaard is not presenting an epistemological theory at all, but through his pseudonymous authors emphasis upon subjectivity he hopes that nominal Christians will begin to experience the need for Christ. Kierkgaard believes that only if inauthentic Christians realize that the religious option cannot be decided by logical inquiry into the doctrines of faith, and then experience their own inauthenticity and the futility of any unaided willful efforts to remedy it, will the act of faith in Christ as a viable alternative appear as reasonable.

F. Russell Sullivan Jr.: author's other books


Who wrote Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
FAITH AND REASON IN
KIERKEGAARD

F. Russell Sullivan, Jr.

Copyright 2010 by University Press of America Inc 4501 Forbes Boulevard - photo 1

Copyright 2010 by

University Press of America, Inc.

4501 Forbes Boulevard

Suite 200

Lanham, Maryland 20706

UPA Acquisitions Department (301) 459-3366

Estover Road

Plymouth PL6 7PY

United Kingdom

All rights reserved

Printed in the United States of America

British Library Cataloging in Publication Information Available

Library of Congress Control Number: 2009936277

ISBN: 978-0-7618-4934-6 (paperback : alk. paper)

eISBN: 978-0-7618-4935-3

Picture 2The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information SciencesPermanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1992

For

JUDITH ANN

RUSTYDAVID
SCOTTPAUL
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

My interest in Kierkegaard grew out of a long standing conviction that he was not a wild-eyed advocate of the absurdity of faith, and that criticisms of him as such from respected philosophical sources did not stand up under a careful and scholarly analysis of his works. I am indebted to Professor Bernard Elevitch of the philosophy department at Boston University who extended himself on my behalf at a very trying and crucial stage of his professional career. His efforts were invaluable in the difficult task that beset me: to show that such an unorthodox pleader of the Christian faith is, in reality, writing (albeit implicibly) to delineate how the movement of faith is a reasonable one. My deep appreciation also to Professors John Lavely, Nancy Lewis, Roger Richards and Sheila Shively for their support.

Finally, words are inadequate to express the feelings of indebtedness to my wife, Judith Ann. Since I began my career in Philosophy in 1966, she has been a constant source of support. During this period, three of our sons were born. The nature of that support has been given added meaning in that, despite the loss of two of our sons, her devotion and steadfastness did not diminish. It is primarily to her I dedicate this work.

INTRODUCTION

The purpose of this work is to clarify Kierkegaards use of reason in the act of faith and to distinguish the special sense of reason that must be understood to appreciate fully Kierkegaards purpose in writing. I hope to show that Kierkegaard does not denigrate every use of reason in the act of faith; in actuality he sees faith as a reasonable enterprise based on the human predicament. As we shall see, it is Kierkegaards intent to persuade those whom he considers nominal Christians (because they appreciate only the doctrinal value of faith) to appreciate faith as a viable alternative to the spiritless condition that Kierkegaard feels permeates their lives. His aim is to present Christianity in a new light to those of his age. An authentic movement of faith is the result of individual self-awareness (sin). Only then can faith be assessed as the reasonable act of choosing Christ rather than the continuation of an inauthentic mode of existing (sin). The reasonableness of faith consists in nominal Christians evisaging it as a prudential choice, rather than as the result of understanding the historical and doctrinal aspects of Christianity. In truth, Kierkegaard sees the latter as secondary. Faith is, in this sense, not the result of a logical argument which supports the fact of the God-man in history. For Kierkegaard, no argument pro or contra can be convincing in this regard. Faith, then, is alogical on the doctrinal level. The fact of the Incarnation cannot be comprehended as true or false by means of logical argumentation. Although reason recognizes its own limitations, it is confronted with the evidence of sin and the Christian message, which essentially is a dialogue between Christ and man concerning this spiritual condition. Faith, then, is not just a reasonable wager in the Pascalian sense. Reason points to faith as a possible answer to mans predicament despite its limitations in reaching logical certainty concerning the doctrines of faith. Therefore, on the more important level, that of encountering and opting for Christianity once a true assessment of self is made, faith is a reasonable undertaking, though not a logical one in the above sense.

To support my view that Kierkegaards view of Christian faith is reasonable, I must distinguish the disparate purposes of Kierkegaards aesthetic (pseudonymous) writings and his non-aesthetic ones ().

Kierkegaard hopes that introspective evidence will lead individuals to an awareness of sin. For Kierkegaard, man is not only in sin; he is dominated by it; man can do nothing about his inauthentic state. Though Christians have an appreciation of the doctrinal value of Christianity, any viable faith must have as a necessary condition their individual awareness of sin; this is gained only by seeing that authentic Christianity begins with introspection and its resultant insights. Kierkegaard sees that only by having nominal Christians view Christianity as alogical in nature on the doctrinal level and themselves as inauthentic (dominated by sin) can they begin to will a change in their beings. Through his aesthetic and psychological works, Kierkegaard hopes to have shown that there is no logical or existential avenue to authenticity. Neither mans understanding of the tenets of faith nor his own unaided willed action can effect a change in his inauthentic state.

In my analysis of some of Kierkegaards religious works (), I shall present evidence of Kierkegaards envisaging Christianity as just this reasonable alternative to mans existential and logical predicament. Although logic fails and he himself can do nothing concerning his state, the nominal Christian has the opportunity to will a change in his being by opting for the escape that Christianity offers. The Incarnation cannot be defended on logical grounds, but faith in Christ as a possible remedy for the sinful nature of man and as the only viable alternative for those Christians of his day is reasonable.

Kierkegaards unique notion of subjectivity is now seen as an effective tool in his attempt to have the Christians of his day view faith as a reasonable undertaking (of the ethical life, but is only hopeful of having nominal Christians begin the introspective movement so that the reasonable aspect of faith can be gleaned by such individuals.

My conclusion () is an explication of Kierkegaards assessment of faith as reasonable, which evolves from my analysis in the first four chapters. It is important to stress the fact that Kierkegaard is not interested in advancing the truth of Christianity vis--vis any other faith. He is writing only for those nominal Christians who have at least a modicum of appreciation of Christian doctrine. Kierkegaard sees Christian faith as a risk, but he is attempting to make his readers see that risk as a calculated one. Christian truth, of which Kierkegaard is convinced, must initially be won by an act that has only the motivation of a potential cure for the spiritual crisis at hand. But Kierkegaard thinks this is enough. His purpose in writing is to afford those existents who have come to terms with their spiritual condition an opportunity to see Christ as a possible Healer, and to will accordingly.

Kierkegaards justification of faith in Christ is one that consists of two exclusive alternatives for the individuals whom he hopes to have drawn to an awareness of their spiritual plight. A confrontation with these two options--the possible discovery of authentic selfhood through the leap of faith as opposed to the continuation of ones inauthentic state of being--is the aim of Kierkegaards explication of the notions of the paradoxical nature of faith, dread, despair and subjectivity.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard»

Look at similar books to Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard»

Discussion, reviews of the book Faith And Reason In Kierkegaard and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.