• Complain

Godelier - Rationality and Irrationality in Economics

Here you can read online Godelier - Rationality and Irrationality in Economics full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2014, publisher: Verso Books, genre: Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover
  • Book:
    Rationality and Irrationality in Economics
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Verso Books
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2014
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Rationality and Irrationality in Economics: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Rationality and Irrationality in Economics" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

This book is the result of a research project begun by the author in 1958 with the aim of answering two questions: First, what is the rationality of the economic systems that appear and disappear throughout historyin other words, what is their hidden logic and the underlying necessity for them to exist, or to have existed Second, what are the conditions for a rational understanding of these systemsin other words, for a fully developed comparative economic science The field of investigation opened up by these two questions is vast, touching on the foundations of social reality and on how to understand them. The author, being a Marxist, sought the answers, as he writes, not in philosophy or by philosophical means, but in and through examining the knowledge accumulated by the sciences. The stages of his journey from philosophy to economics and then to anthropology are indicated by the divisions of his book. Godelier rejects, at the outset, any attempt to tackle the question of rationality or irrationality of economic science and of economic realities from the angle of an a priori idea, a speculative definition of what is rational. Such an approach can yield only, he feels, an ideological result. Rather, he treats the appearance and disappearance of social and economic systems in history as being governed by a necessity wholly internal to the concrete structures of social life.

Godelier: author's other books


Who wrote Rationality and Irrationality in Economics? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Rationality and Irrationality in Economics — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Rationality and Irrationality in Economics" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Published by Verso 2012 Verso 2012 Published by New Left Books 1972 Translation - photo 1
Published by Verso 2012 Verso 2012 Published by New Left Books 1972 Translation - photo 2

Published by Verso 2012
Verso 2012
Published by New Left Books 1972
Translation Brian Pearce 1972
First published as Rationalit et irrationalit en conomie
Franois Maspero 1966

All rights reserved

The moral rights of the authors have been asserted

Verso
UK: 6 Meard Street, London W1F 0EG
US: 20 Jay Street, Suite 1010, Brooklyn, NY 11201
www.versobooks.com

Verso is the imprint of New Left Books

eBook ISBN: 978-1-78168-037-7
Trade Paperback ISBN: 978-1-78168-025-4

British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress

v3.1

Foreword to the English edition (1972)
Functionalism, Structuralism and Marxism
THE SCOPE OF THE QUESTION AND THE COURSES FOLLOWED

When this book was published in 1966 it offered an interim report on a task of research that had been begun in 1958, with the aim of finding the answer to two questions which are really only a single question: What is the rationality of the economic systems that appear and disappear throughout history in other words, what is their hidden logic and the underlying necessity for them to exist, or to have existed: and what are the conditions needed for a rational understanding of these systems in other words, for a fully-developed comparative economic science?

Here was a question that, though precise, led me into a field of research that seemed unlimited, being defined by no boundaries either de jure or de facto ; a question the vastness of which showed clearly enough that it had been advanced by a philosopher that is, by a mind given to focusing directly upon basic truths, concerned with the foundations of reality and of how we know them. At the same time, however and here the philosopher who put forward this huge question showed that he was no longer a philosopher of the traditional sort, but a Marxist the answer to this question was not sought in philosophy or by philosophical means , but in and through examining the knowledge accumulated by the sciences, and a variety of theoretical methods. Hence the strange journey from philosophy to economics, and then to anthropology, the stages of which are indicated by the texts assembled in this book.

I thus had twice to apply myself to learning a new theoretical method, and to endeavouring to find out if the question of rationality still meant something, and what the new forms were in which it presented itself. If, however, it proved necessary to go beyond political economy to anthropology, this was because the former, as it exists today, restricts itself to analysing two contemporary economic systems, and for it the question of economic rationality leads ineluctably to the assertion, increasingly supported by proofs, of the superiority of one system over the other, and the necessity for one of them (this one or that) to vanquish the other in the course of historical development. I therefore had to subject to critical examination the evidence adduced by the advocates of each system and to seek the conditions needed if this evidence was to contribute scientific and not ideological proof.

In this search for the epistemological conditions of a rigorous proof, one conclusion became obvious at an early stage, namely, that the question of the rationality of a system means primarily the question of the historical necessity for its existence in other words, in order to think out this question one has to construct the theory of the conditions for the systems appearance and development, something that is usually excluded from, or kept outside, the field of research of political economy and left to the historians of economic life. A second conclusion emerges, as an extension of the first: the conditions for the rise, functioning and evolution of any system are twofold, some belonging to the sphere of mens intentional activity, while others, of more decisive importance, give expression to the unintentional properties inherent in social relations, properties that do not belong to mens consciousness, having neither their origin nor their basis in that sphere, and that are latent with the possibility of transforming these social relations.

If, however, economic and social systems are mutually contradictory, and if each of them develops and changes and eventually vanishes from history, this is because no system exists or can reproduce itself elsewhere than within definite limits , by way of transformations that are compatible with the unintentional properties of its inner structures these limits being merely the ways in which these unintentional properties, and the relations of functional compatibility and incompatibility determined by them, are manifested. It was therefore necessary to bring these concepts of compatibility, incompatibility and limits into relation with the concept of contradiction and the concepts of systems-theory and cybernetics. This was how I started on my investigation of the concepts of correspondence and contradiction between structures, and my criticism of ideas derived either from Hegel or from Marx as he has been misrepresented by dogmatic Marxism.

The ultimate question still stood, however: is there an ultimate reason, an ultimate basis for the transformations that economic systems undergo, transformations that are governed by the relations of compatibility and incompatibility between the structures composing these systems? And since (unless we are to assume that history is given meaning from outside itself and is driven by some a priori purpose) this basis has to be looked for within the various types of relations that obtain among men, the question then becomes: which, among these relations, are the ones that bear primary responsibility for the major transformations that occur in the history of mankind, determining them in the last analysis ? Among the possible answers to this question, we know the one offered by Marx: the relations that men form among themselves in order to carry out, and in the process of carrying out, the production of the material conditions of their existence determine, in the last analysis, the relations of compatibility and incompatibility between all levels of social life and, therefore, it is the major transformations that take place in the material conditions of their existence that determine, in the last analysis, the outstanding transformations that occur in the forms and functions of the other levels of social life (political, ideological, etc.).

There seemed, however, to be an unavoidable objection to this answer offered by Marx. How could this hypothesis be reconciled with the fact for example, that within many primitive societies it is relations of kinship between men that dominate social organization (Radcliffe-Brown, Evans-Pritchard), or that religious relations seem to dominate Indian society, dividing men into a hierarchy of castes in accordance with an ideology of purity and impurity (Louis Dumont)?

Thus, unless facts were to be dogmatically denied and treated as hallucinations, the Marxist problematic in the sphere of economic and social science, concerned with accounting for the existence and variety of societies and their history, became: how are we to conceive the relations between the determining structure and the dominant one, and what determining power in economic relations is it that dictates that there shall be dominance by kinship-relations or by politico-religious relations? This question could not be answered, or even asked, by dogmatic Marxism and the other forms of that vulgar materialism to which dogmatic Marxism belongs, even though it denies the affinity. For vulgar materialism, the economy, which it reduces to the relations between technology and environment, produces the given society, giving rise to it as an epiphenomenon. This means refusing to see the irreducible differences between the levels and structures of social life, the reason for the relative autonomy with which they operate, and reducing all levels to so many functions, either apparent or concealed, of economic activity. One example will suffice to show the dead-end that vulgar materialism plunges into, thus enabling various idealist theories of society and history to triumph over its helplessness. In kinship-relations, whatever form they may take, there is an element that can never be reduced to a mere economic relation or deduced exclusively from such a relation. This is the relation between individuals of opposite sexes who cooperate, in a socially regulated relationship, namely, marriage, to ensure the biological reproduction of society. Clearly, it depends on definite conditions of the production of material existence whether the division between the sexes is or is not the dominant form of the division of labour, and whether it is relations of consanguinity within a group or marriage-relations between groups that constitute the means of direct cooperation in production or indirect cooperation in the circulation of goods: but, from the outset, kinship relations are not reduced to the effecting of these functions alone, and for this reason it is not possible simply to deduce then from the latter. It therefore seems clear to me that only if we radically reject vulgar materialism can we hope to tackle correctly the task of analysing the relations between determination and dominance, and so to establish, so far as some societies are concerned, the working of the structural causality of their various modes of production in relation to their organization and evolution.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Rationality and Irrationality in Economics»

Look at similar books to Rationality and Irrationality in Economics. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Rationality and Irrationality in Economics»

Discussion, reviews of the book Rationality and Irrationality in Economics and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.