Dworkin - Taking rights seriously
Here you can read online Dworkin - Taking rights seriously full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. City: London, USA, United States, year: 2013, publisher: Bloomsbury Academic, genre: Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:
Romance novel
Science fiction
Adventure
Detective
Science
History
Home and family
Prose
Art
Politics
Computer
Non-fiction
Religion
Business
Children
Humor
Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.
Taking rights seriously: summary, description and annotation
We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Taking rights seriously" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.
Dworkin: author's other books
Who wrote Taking rights seriously? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.
Taking rights seriously — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work
Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Taking rights seriously" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.
Font size:
Interval:
Bookmark:
Taking Rights Seriously
TITLES IN THE BLOOMSBURY REVELATIONS SERIES
Aesthetic Theory , Theodor W. Adorno
On Religion, Karl Barth
The Intelligence of Evil , Jean Baudrillard
In Defence of Politics , Bernard Crick
Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy , Manuel DeLanda
A Thousand Plateaus , Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari
Anti-Oedipus , Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari
Taking Rights Seriously , Ronald Dworkin
Discourse on Free Will , Desiderius Erasmus and Martin Luther
Education for Critical Consciousness , Paulo Freire
To Have or To Be? , Erich Fromm
Truth and Method , Hans Georg Gadamer
All Men Are Brothers , Mohandas K. Gandhi
Eclipse of Reason , Max Horkheimer
After Virtue , Alasdair MacIntyre
Time for Revolution, Antonio Negri
The Politics of Aesthetics , Jacques Ranciere
An Actor Prepares , Constantin Stanislavski
Building a Character , Constantin Stanislavski
Creating a Role , Constantin Stanislavski
Some titles are not available in North America.
Taking Rights Seriously
Ronald Dworkin
Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc
50 Bedford Square | 175 Fifth Avenue |
London | New York |
WC1B 3DP | NY 10010 |
UK | USA |
www.bloomsbury.com
First published in 1977 by Gerald Duckworth & Co Ltd; New edition published 1997
This paperback edition first published in 2013 by Bloomsbury Academic
Ronald Dworkin 1977, 1997
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers.
No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the author.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
ePub ISBN: 978-1-7809-3833-2
Typeset by Deanta Global Publishing Services, Chennai, India
Contents
The chapters of this book were written separately during a period of great political controversy about what law is and who must obey it and when. During the same period the political attitude called liberalism, once the posture of almost all politicians, seemed to lose a great deal of its appeal. The middle-aged blamed liberalism for permissiveness and the young blamed it for rigidity, economic injustice and the war in Vietnam. Uncertainty about law reflected uncertainty about a conventional political attitude.
The various chapters define and defend a liberal theory of law. They are nevertheless sharply critical of another theory that is widely thought to be a liberal theory. This theory has been so popular and influencial that I shall call it the ruling theory of law. The ruling theory has two parts, and insists on their independence. The first is a theory about what law is; in less dramatic language it is a theory about the necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of a proposition of law. This is the theory of legal positivism, which holds that the truth of legal propositions consists in facts about the rules that have been adopted by specific social institutions, and in nothing else. The second is a theory about what the law ought to be, and how the familiar legal institutions ought to behave. This is the theory of utilitarianism, which holds that law and its institutions should serve the general welfare, and nothing else. Both parts of the ruling theory derive from the philosophy of Jeremy Bentham.
The critical portions of these essays criticize both parts of the theory, and also criticize the assumption that they are independent of one another. The constructive portions emphasize an idea that is also part of the liberal tradition, but that has no place in either legal positivism or utilitarianism. This is the old idea of individual human rights. Bentham called that idea nonsense on stilts.
A general theory of law must be normative as well as conceptual. Its normative part must treat a variety of topics indicated by the following catalogue. It must have a theory of legislation, of adjudication, and of compliance; these three theories look at the normative questions of law from the standpoints of a lawmaker, a judge, and an ordinary citizen. The theory of legislation must contain a theory of legitimacy, which describes the circumstances under which a particular person or group is entitled to make law, and a theory of legislative justice, which describes the law they are entitled or obliged to make. The theory of adjudication must also be complex: it must contain a theory of controversy, which sets out standards that judges should use to decide hard cases at law, and a theory of jurisdiction, which explains why and when judges, rather than other groups or institutions, should make the decisions required by the theory of controversy. The theory of compliance must contrast and discuss two roles. It must contain a theory of deference, which discusses the nature and limits of the citizens duty to obey the law in different forms of state, and under different circumstances, and a theory of enforcement, which identifies the goals of enforcement and punishment, and describes how officials should respond to different categories of crime or fault.
A general theory of law will comprehend subjects that do not fall within any of these categories, and a topic that falls within one may fall within others as well. The politically sensitive issue of constitutionalism is, for example, an issue in the theory of legitimacy. Why should the elected representatives of the majority ever be disabled from enacting law that seems to them fair and efficient? But a related question is also an issue in the conceptual part of a legal theory. Can the most fundamental principles of the constitution, which define who is competent to make law and how, themselves be considered as part of the law? That conceptual question plainly bears on other questions of legitimacy and jurisdiction. If the political principles embedded in the constitution are law, then the title of judges to decide what the constitution requires is, at least prima facie, confirmed; if these principles are law in spite of the fact that they are not the product of deliberate social or political decision, then the fact that law can be, in that sense, natural argues for the constraint on majority power that a constitution imposes. Both the conceptual question and the questions of jurisdiction and legitimacy bear in obvious ways on the theory of compliance; they bear, for example, on the issue of whether a dissident can plausibly or even coherently say that his idea of what the fundamental law of the constitution requires may be superior to that of the legislature and the judges.
The interdependencies of the various parts of a general theory of law are therefore complex. In the same way, moreover, a general theory of law will have many connections with other departments of philosophy. The normative theory will be embedded in a more general political and moral philosophy which may in turn depend upon philosophical theories about human nature or the objectivity of morality. The conceptual part will draw upon the philosophy of language and therefore upon logic and metaphysics. The issue of what propositions of law mean, and whether they are always true or false, for example, establishes immediate connections with very difficult and controverted questions in philosophical logic. A general theory of law must therefore constantly take up one or another disputed position on problems of philosophy that are not distinctly legal.
Next pageFont size:
Interval:
Bookmark:
Similar books «Taking rights seriously»
Look at similar books to Taking rights seriously. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.
Discussion, reviews of the book Taking rights seriously and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.