• Complain

Bunzl - Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change

Here you can read online Bunzl - Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2015, publisher: Taylor and Francis;Routledge, genre: Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Bunzl Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change
  • Book:
    Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Taylor and Francis;Routledge
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2015
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

When it comes to climate change, the greatest difficulty we face is that we do not know the likely degree of change or its cost, which means that environmental policy decisions have to be made under uncertainty. This book offers an accessible philosophical treatment of the broad range of ethical and policy challenges posed by climate change uncertainty.

Drawing on both the philosophy of science and ethics, Martin Bunzl shows how tackling climate change revolves around weighing up our interests now against those of future generations, which requires that we examine our assumptions about the value of present costs versus future benefits. In an engaging, conversational style, Bunzl looks at questions such as our responsibility towards non-human life, the interests of the developing and developed worlds, and how the circumstances of poverty shape the perception of risk, ultimate developing and defending a view of humanity and its place in the world that makes sense of our duty to Nature without treating it as a rights bearer.

This book will be of interest to students and scholars of environmental studies, philosophy, politics and sociology as well as policy makers.

Bunzl: author's other books


Who wrote Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
1
Risk and the Perception of Risk
I

Policy questions about avoiding climate change involve decisions under, at best, uncertainty. Our difficulty is that we dont know the likely degree of climate change, nor its cost. But these limitations on our knowledge may seem no different than those infecting many of the decisions we have to make on a daily basis.

I am 65 years old and have no long-term care insurance. Should I buy some? It is a question I have asked myself on and off for the last 10 years, but my decision remains unresolved. It is a hard decision to make, if only for psychological reasons. A desire for a quick death, or alternatively, immortality, clouds the decision. Bracketing psychological considerations, should I buy the insurance? As with all insurance, it is a decision under uncertainty. But it is one for which statistical data is available. There are enough data points that I can fine grain the data base as much as I want to derive a sample that is very much like me, even if it is not identical with me. Of course how much to fine grain is a matter of discretion, and one that may not matter too much depending on how little doing so changes the distribution of the results. Those results will give me a figure for the probability that I will need to use the policy at some point in future. What is much harder to decide on is this: what the value of the insurance is in dollars on the day I pay the premium. The benefit is in dollars in the future (if a payout is triggered), unless I have a stroke before the day on which the policy becomes effective. What discount rate should I apply to normalize the difference between the two? Suppose I pay $10,000 in a lump sum now and use the policy 10 years from now for a year, garnering $20,000 in benefits after which I die. The present value of that benefit is not $20,000 but the amount of capital that would yield $20,000 in 10 years if invested. How much that is depends on what I assume the rate of return to be. The present value (PV$) of $20,000 10 years from now is a function of the (inflation adjusted) interest rates (IR%):

IR%PV$
413,500
512,000
611,000
710,000

Suppose I use the average rate of return on my retirement portfolio as a guide. Then the worth of the policy today is a function of the net present value of the payout for each year and the probability that I will use it in that year.

Are we then done? Not quite. There are additional considerations that may be relevant to how much to discount the value of a future payout. So far, all we have considered is essentially the inflation-adjusted opportunity cost of spending money on a premium instead of investing it. But the value of a dollar now as opposed to in the future is also a function of technology. Technological advances reduce the cost of living. So, $20,000 in 10 years may buy more than it does now, despite the effects of inflation. If I want to buy care worth $20,000 in 10 years based on current technology, on this consideration, I can plan to pay less for the same care in the future in real dollars. So I can further discount those dollars in the present. Finally, there is this to consider: maybe a dollar spent now is worth more to me than a dollar spent 10 years from now.

There is a good reason to ignore this last consideration, if only for my own (long-term) good. Money tends to burn a hole in my pocket and hence I tend to overdiscount the value of future money. But there other reasons that look more legitimate. I value life more now than I expect to value it in the future because I am younger and more vibrant now. I, literally, get more out of life. It is not that money spent caring for me in the future will be worth less than money spent on (say) wine and music now but that, all other things being equal , the value to me of a dollar then and now will be different. Still other reasons are not obviously illegitimate but not obviously legitimate either. I care about me now more than I care about the me that will be in the future. It is the kind of sentiment that tempts me not to go to the gym and diet. No doubt a life led now without excess will yield benefits to my future self, but I find it hard not to discount the value of my future self relative to my self now.

These complications notwithstanding, making such a decision under uncertainty for an individual is reasonably straightforward. And it might seem that extending the approach to collective decision making ought to be no less straightforward. That is certainly true if we stick to one generation. But as soon as the collective decision involves more than one generation things get more complicated.

Deciding whether or not to buy insurance involves two very distinct components: one is epistemic. That implicates both the matter of setting a value for the likelihood of particular outcomes and some features that go into setting a value on the discount rate, like the rate of return on capital and the rate of technological innovation. But the other component is purely valuational, as when I am forced to decide how much to care about the future as opposed to the present.

When we think of decision making across generations, the epistemic challenge does not change in kind but does in complexity. Time is our enemy here. The further our horizon of concern, the less confident we can be about our assignment of probabilities. It is one thing to extrapolate from a subset of the population now to another subset of the population now, and quite another thing to do the same thing across time and more so, the larger the swath of time. (For example, think how much both life expectancy and technology have changed in the last 100 years.) But when it comes to matters of valuation, a much deeper issue intrudes. My quandary about whether or not to buy long-term care insurance was a conflict between my interests now and my interests in the future. But when it comes to climate change, the tradeoff between interests is between us now and others in the future. That seems to turn a calculus of self-interest into a matter of altruism.

Still, to the extent that we think of our government as representing our collective self-interest, not only in time but across time, maybe the calculus of self-interest can be preserved. If we think of each generation as benefiting from the sacrifices of the previous generation, there is still always a temptation for each of us, as individuals, to break with the implicit compact between generations. We harvest the slow growing trees they planted, but fail to replant new ones. We benefit from the practical results of their costly theoretical research, but fail to fund such ongoing research at an appropriate level. We cross the bridges designed to last 100 years that they built, but fail to renew them as they become worn down. Yet knowing we are subject to such inclinations, we rely on our government to act on behalf of our better selves. We look to them to act in our self-interest where the our reaches out across generations. But be that as it may, such government action still has to depend on citizen support in the here and now and, whether based on self-interest or altruism, such support depends on our perception of how things are. So when a government acts in a way that may seem to be in the collective interest, it cant avoid dealing with how individuals see things.

II

I used to smoke and I enjoyed doing so very much. I gave up after my doctor told me it might kill me. Might was enough to convince me that the pleasure did not outweigh the risks. For all I know it may have turned out that his warnings were misplaced. Maybe the correlation between smoking and disease will turn out to be spurious the result of a common cause. But the uncertainty gets swamped out by the costs of being wrong. The cost of death to me is high. High enough that even if there is only a small chance of my doctor being right, I want to avoid it. And the price of avoiding it, foregoing the pleasure, pales in comparison to that. Assume my actions are rational when it comes to smoking. What prevents their extension to averting climate change? One difference is this: the statistical data on the risks of smoking are well established in a way that is observer independent. They are a function of the frequency of death among smokers as compared to non-smokers. Of course we have to control for all sorts of other things, but all other things being equal, the effect of smoking on the chance of dying is similar to the effect of adding 5 to 10 years of age (Woloshin et al. 2008, 845). Moreover, the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention estimates that on average, smoking reduces life expectancy by between 13 and 14 years (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention 2002). Yet when it comes to making an individual decision about whether to smoke or not, what matters is not what the observer independent risk is, but on what the perceived risk by the individual is. That subjective perception of risk (and with it cost) is what matters when it comes to making a decision based on the costs and benefits. So, even if what I will call the objective risk of not acting to avoid climate change might be the same as the objective risk of continuing to smoke, the perception of risk, the subjective risk, might be different. And indeed, the literature on risk perception gives ample reason to think that it will be different.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change»

Look at similar books to Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change»

Discussion, reviews of the book Uncertainty and the Philosophy of Climate Change and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.