• Complain

Stephen Holmes - The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes

Here you can read online Stephen Holmes - The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 1999, publisher: W. W. Norton & Company, genre: Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover

The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

All legally enforceable rights cost money. This is a practical, common sense notion but one ignored by almost everyone. To fight for your rights, or anyone elses, is not just to debate principles but to haggle over budgets. Most conservatives imagine that rights our exercised to property, speech, and religion free of government interference. Yet such rights would not exist if the government could not collect taxes to codify, protect and enforce them. Meanwhile, most liberals prefer to avoid the harsh reality that spending resources on some rights means not spending them on other, perhaps more valuable, rights. The insights that rights are expensive is a reminder that freedom is not violated by a government that taxes and spends. Rather, freedom requires such government and requires a citizenry vigilant about how money is allocated. This work seeks to change the terms of the USAs critical and contentious political debates.

Stephen Holmes: author's other books


Who wrote The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

ALSO BY S TEPHEN H OLMES Passions and Constraint Anatomy of Antiliberalism - photo 1

ALSO BY S TEPHEN H OLMES

Passions and Constraint

Anatomy of Antiliberalism

Benjamin Constant and the Making of Modern Liberalism

ALSO BY C ASS R. S UNSTEIN

Free Markets and Social Justice

Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict

The Partial Constitution

After the Rights Revolution

Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech

One Case at a Time: Judicial Minimalism on the Supreme Court

T HE C OST
OF R IGHTS

Why Liberty Depends on Taxes

W W Norton Company New York London T O G EOFFREY S TONE C ONTENTS A - photo 2

W. W. Norton & Company
New York London

T O G EOFFREY S TONE

C ONTENTS

A CKNOWLEDGMENTS

I T IS A KEEN PLEASURE to thank the many friends and colleagues who helped us with this book. We first stumbled across the cost of rights, as a subject for inquiry and analysis, in discussions at the Center on Constitutionalism in Eastern Europe at the University of Chicago. A healthy respect for the fiscal preconditions of effective rights enforcement arose naturally from observing the underprotection of basic liberties in the insolvent states of Eastern Europe and the former Soviet Union. Russias great experiment with the jury trial, to choose a typical example, went awry when it began to consume 25 percent of already inadequate local court budgets. One of our principal goals here has been to apply what we learned in this eye-opening context to the debate about rights underway in the United States. We thank Dwight Semler, the coordinator of the Center, and our co-directors, Jon Elster, Larry Lessig, and Wiktor Osiatynski, as well as Andras Sajo, for many challenging discussions. We are also grateful for searching criticisms and wily suggestions on the manuscript from Elster, Bruce Ackerman, Samuel Beer, Martin Krygier, Martha Nussbaum, Richard Posner, and Bernard Yack. Sophie Clark, Keith Sharfman, Matthew Utterbeck, and Christian Lucky provided invaluable research assistance. Appreciation also goes to our editor, Alane Salierno Mason, for her incisive comments and steady encouragement.

Introduction:

C OMMON S ENSE ABOUT R IGHTS

O N AUGUST 26, 1995, a fire broke out in Westhampton, on the westernmost edge of the celebrated Long Island Hamptons, one of the most beautiful areas in the United States. This fire was the worst experienced by New York in the past half-century. For thirty-six hours it raged uncontrollably, at one point measuring six miles by twelve.

But this story has a happy ending. In a remarkably short time, local, state, and federal forces moved in to quell the blaze. Officials and employees from all levels of government descended upon the scene. More than fifteen hundred local volunteer firefighters joined with military and civilian teams from across the state and country. Eventually, the fire was brought under control. Astonishingly, no one was killed. Equally remarkably, destruction of property was minimal. Volunteerism helped, but in the end, public resources made this rescue possible. Ultimate costs to American taxpayers, local and national, originally estimated at $1.1 million, may have been as high as $2.9 million.

Opposition to government has been a defining theme of American populism in the late twentieth century. Its slogan is, Dont tread on me! Or as Ronald Reagan put it, Government isnt the solution; its the problem. More recently, critics of all things governmental, such as Charles Murray and David Boaz, have claimed that an adult making an honest living and minding his own business deserves to be left alone, and that the real problem in the United States is the same one being recognized all over the world: too much government.

Yet in Westhampton, on the spur of the moment, public officials were able to organize and direct a costly and collective effort to defend private property, drawing liberally on public resources contributed by the citizenry at large, for the emergency rescue of real estate owned by a relatively small number of wealthy families.

There is nothing exceptional about this story. In 1996, American taxpayers devoted at least $11.6 billion to protecting private property by means of disaster relief and disaster insurance.

Public support for the kind of safety net that benefited the home owners of Westhampton is broad and deep, but at the same time, Americans seem easily to forget that individual rights and freedoms depend fundamentally on vigorous state action. Without effective government, American citizens would not be able to enjoy their private property in the way they do. Indeed, they would enjoy few or none of their constitutionally guaranteed individual rights. Personal liberty, as Americans value and experience it, presupposes social cooperation managed by government officials. The private realm we rightly prize is sustained, indeed created, by public action. Not even the most self-reliant citizen is asked to look after his or her material welfare autonomously, without any support from fellow citizens or public officials.

The story of the Westhampton fire is the story of property ownership across America and, in truth, throughout the world. Indeed, it is the story of all liberal rights. When structured constitutionally and made (relatively speaking) democratically responsive, government is an indispensable device for mobilizing and channeling effectively the diffuse resources of the community, bringing them to bear on problems, in pinpoint operations, whenever these unexpectedly flare up.

The Declaration of Independence states that to secure these rights, Governments are established among men. To the obvious truth that rights depend on government must be added a logical corollary, one rich with implications: rights cost money. Rights cannot be protected or enforced without public funding and support. This is just as true of old rights as of new rights, of the rights of Americans before as well as after Franklin Delano Roosevelts New Deal. Both the right to welfare and the right to private property have public costs. The right to freedom of contract has public costs no less than the right to health care, the right to freedom of speech no less than the right to decent housing. All rights make claims upon the public treasury.

The cost of rights is a richly ambiguous phrase because both words have multiple and inevitably controversial meanings. To keep the analysis as focused and, along this dimension, as uncontentious as possible, costs will be understood here to mean budgetary costs and rights will be defined as important interests that can be reliably protected by individuals or groups using the instrumentalities of government . Both definitions require elaboration.

D EFINING R IGHTS

The term rights has many referents and shades of meaning. There are, broadly speaking, two distinct ways to approach the subject: moral and descriptive. The first associates rights with moral principles or ideals. It identifies rights not by consulting statutes and case law, but by asking what human beings are morally entitled to. While no single agreed-upon theory of such moral rights exists, some of the most interesting philosophical work on rights involves an ethical inquiry, evaluative in nature, of this general kind. Moral philosophy conceives of nonlegal rights as moral claims of the strongest sort, enjoyed perhaps by virtue of ones status or capacity as a moral agent, not as a result of ones membership in, or legal relationship to, a particular political society. The moral account of rights tries to identify those human interests that may not, before the tribunal of conscience, ever be neglected or intruded upon without special justification.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes»

Look at similar books to The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes»

Discussion, reviews of the book The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.