• Complain

David Estlund - The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy

Here you can read online David Estlund - The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2012, publisher: Oxford University Press, genre: Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover
  • Book:
    The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Oxford University Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2012
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Even though political philosophy has a long tradition, it is much more than the study of old and great treatises. Contemporary philosophers continue to press new arguments on old and timeless questions, but also to propose departures and innovations. The field changes over time, and new work inevitably responds both to events in the world and to the directions of thought itself. This volume includes 22 new pieces by leaders in the field on both perennial and emerging topics of keen interest to contemporary political philosophers. In addition to longstanding issues such as Authority, Equality, and Freedom, and Democracy, there are articles on less classical topics such as Race, Historical Injustice, Deliberation, Money and Politics, Global Justice, and Ideal and Non-Ideal Theory. All of the pieces combine clarity and accessibility with a top scholars critical and original point of view. The introductory essay briefly situates this snapshot of the state of the art in a broader view of developments in political philosophy in the last 40 years, and looks forward to future developments. Students and scholars alike will find the pieces to be valuable not only surveys but as provocations to think further about the questions, puzzles, and practical problems that animate recent work in political philosophy. The issues will be of interest to many working in philosophy, political science, law, economics, and more.

David Estlund: author's other books


Who wrote The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Introduction
David Estlund

Several people, taking a single photograph at the same place and the same time, will produce as many images as there are photographers, each differing from the others, each freezing a passing moment, and all of them leaving most of the scene outside the frame. My role in commissioning and introducing these articles is similar. The issues that occupy political philosophers change over time and are always broader and more various than can be captured in any survey of the field. Still, a volume such as this one might serve as a sort of snapshot of one stage in this evolution. It is a record and a description, from certain points of view, of part of the shifting intellectual landscape at a certain point in time. The pieces in this volume, written by leaders in the field, are intended both as introductions and as substantial statements that will be of interest to even the most advanced scholars. My aim in this introduction is not to engage in detail with the individual pieces but rather to set out some of the objectives I had in selecting topics and to reflect on what we can learn from these chapters about how the field of political philosophy has evolved and is still evolving.

Political philosophy maintains closer contact, I believe, with the history of its subject than many other areas of philosophy do. Perhaps this is due to the close intermingling of political philosophy with political theory (as practiced in departments of politics, political science, or government) where the historical dimension is especially prominent. I have chosen, nevertheless, to concentrate on the kinds of issues with which the canonical theorists themselves were concerned (when they werent interpreting their own predecessors). So many of the other chapters make contact with their work that it seemed appropriate to include an overview of these two defining figures now that they are sadly gone and their bodies of work complete.

. The Era of Rawls

The work of John Rawls, even more than that of Robert Nozick, continues to exert enormous influence and is mentioned in the text or bibliography of about two-thirds of the chapters in this volume. The pieces were commissioned, of course, and so it is not a random sample of any kind, but I believe this reflects the continuing importance of Rawlss thought in current work in the field of political philosophy. It is certainly central (sometimes, of course, as a foil) to the current debates, as we can see from the chapters in this volume, about equality (see Anderson), justice (see Arneson), classical liberalism (see Tomasi and Brennan), social contract approaches (see Freeman), global justice (see Risse), and ideal and nonideal theory (see Swift and Stemplowska).

Rawls has long figured prominently in a certain received view, which I describe later, of how political philosophy has developed since the 1960s. As time goes on, that familiar story is looking less plausible, or at least greatly exaggerated in certain ways. logical and conceptual clarification. He confronted the great question of social justice head on, striking a chord with activists who were fighting against the sterility of academe.

But there is a puzzle about this story, this emphasis on Rawlss direct engagement with moral issues. When the book came out, students and faculty were clamoring for relevance in their studies. It is true that TJ was less sterile than most philosophy (written in English) of the preceding decades. On the other hand, Rawls himself studiously avoided joining the controversies that rocked American society in the 1960s. His defense of civil disobedience and conscientious refusal to obey certain laws was an exception; even there, he never said how these principles applied to current events. The book (unlike the man, Im told) said nothing directly about the current civil rights controversies, the Vietnam war (the book was mostly finished by the time that war sent students into the streets), or feminism. Yet intellectuals moved by those events were galvanized by the idea that questions of social justice might be situated in such a broad and deep philosophical account, supported by powerful arguments drawing on the whole Western philosophical tradition from Socrates through Rousseau, Kant, Hegel, Marx, and Mill. The puzzle is this: How did such an abstract and learned treatment of the idea of social justice meet the needs of that turbulent and impatient time?

From his very earliest writing, Rawls wondered whether the contenders in certain reasonable but intractable controversies could be brought to see that they shared many important assumptions. If they could, then they might pursue their differences more productively on that common basis. At the beginning, the controversies he tried to steer around were esoteric philosophical disputes about the nature and knowability of moral claims in general. (Are all moral claims merely subjective in some way? Is there a moral reality independent of our moral thoughts? Can moral claims be logically derived from nonmoral ones?) In his later writing, the contentious disputes he sought to circumvent were those that arose when political actions were defended on the basis of sectarian religious principles or other deep convictions about the meaning of life.

In his other major book, Political Liberalism, Rawls (1993) spoke of philosophys potential for reconciliation, though this can easily be misunderstood. Reconciliation can be a tepid, shameful stance when some of the contenders in the conflict are contemptible. Rawls loved the example of Lincolns decision to go to war as the only way to prevent the spread of slavery and the splitting of the nation. Butand here is the familiar moral fact at the very center of Rawlss thought over the yearscontroversies arise even among reasonable, informed, morally decent people. In that case, Rawls thought, there are probably important issues that all sides agree on and important commitments on which their shared decency and reasonableness depend. The identification of that common ground, if it is possible, would promote a kind of reconciliation, although we still could not just retreat to our shared assumptions and avoid the need to make the difficult decisions about which we initially disagreed. The goal was not to banish conflict. But, Rawls thought, if we can find and articulate our shared principles and convictions, adjusting them when necessary to (p. 6) accommodate more specific convictions, at least we might narrow the range of disagreement. Some of the original contending views might turn out to be indefensible; new views might emerge that make better sense of the basic principles. Disagreement might then be pursued more productively.

The search for common ground is an exercise in abstraction, the bracketing of specifics to identify more general similarities and affinities among differing worldviews. The principles Rawls arrives at, then, are more or less familiar and unspecific in practice. This is, in my view, no indictment, but I doubt that Rawls can be appropriated by authors who believe that proper political philosophy should always be addressed to pressing problems and offer practical solutions. Rawlss two principles are, of course, in need of practical interpretation, and his own interpretation includes elements that are less familiar and more controversial than the principles themselves. He writes that justice as fairness leaves open the question whether its principles are best realized by some form of property-owning democracy or by a liberal socialist regime (Rawls , xv). Each of these is conceived as an alternative to capitalism, and he goes to great lengths to distinguish property-owning democracy from the more familiar idea of a welfare state. However, the idea of property-owning democracy was not clarified and elaborated on by Rawls until many years after the publication of

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy»

Look at similar books to The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy»

Discussion, reviews of the book The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.