• Complain

Gabbay Dov M. - Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts

Here you can read online Gabbay Dov M. - Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. City: Boston;Amsterdam, year: 2012, publisher: Elsevier Science;North Holland;Elsevier, genre: Religion. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover

Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

The Handbook of the History of Logic is a multi-volume research instrument that brings to the development of logic the best in modern techniques of historical and interpretative scholarship. It is the first work in English in which the history of logic is presented so extensively. The volumes are numerous and large. Authors have been given considerable latitude to produce chapters of a length, and a level of detail, that would lay fair claim on the ambitions of the project to be a definitive research work. Authors have been carefully selected with this aim in mind. They and the Editors join in the conviction that a knowledge of the history of logic is nothing but beneficial to the subjects present-day research programmes. One of the attractions of the Handbooks several volumes is the emphasis they give to the enduring relevance of developments in logic throughout the ages, including some of the earliest manifestations of the subject.


  • Covers in depth the notion...
  • Gabbay Dov M.: author's other books


    Who wrote Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

    Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

    Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

    Light

    Font size:

    Reset

    Interval:

    Bookmark:

    Make
    Logic A History of its Central Concepts Edited by Dov M Gabbay Department of - photo 1
    Logic: A History of its Central Concepts

    Edited by

    Dov M. Gabbay

    Department of Informatics, Kings College London, UK

    Francis Jeffry Pelletier

    Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta, Canada

    Departments of Philosophy and Linguistics, Simon Fraser University, Canada

    John Woods

    Department of Philosophy, University of British Columbia, Canada

    Department of Philosophy, University of Lethbridge, Canada

    Group on Logic, Information and Computation, Kings College London, UK

    Table of Contents Copyright North Holland is an imprint of Elsevier The - photo 2

    Table of Contents
    Copyright

    North Holland is an imprint of Elsevier

    The Boulevard, Langford lane, Kidlington, Oxford, OX5 1GB, UK

    Radarweg 29, PO Box 211, 1000 AE Amsterdam, The Netherlands

    225 Wyman Street, Waltham, MA 02451, USA

    First edition 2012

    Copyright 2012 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved

    Chapter [9]: Originally published in Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, Volume 8, No. 2, pp. 185245. 2002 Association for Symbolic Logic. Reprinted with permission.

    No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior written permission of the publisher

    Permissions may be sought directly from Elseviers Science & Technology Rights Department in Oxford, UK: phone (+44) (0) 1865 843830; fax (+44) (0) 1865 853333; email: , and selecting Obtaining permission to use Elsevier material

    British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data

    A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress

    ISBN: 978-0-444-52937-4

    ISSN: 1874-5857

    For information on all North Holland publications visit our web site at store.elsevier.com

    Printed and bound in Great Britain

    12 13 14 15 16 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

    Dedication This book is dedicated with gratitude to Jane Spurr and Carol Woods - photo 3

    Dedication

    This book is dedicated with gratitude to Jane Spurr and Carol Woods.

    Preface

    The present volume marks the conclusion of the Handbook of the History of Logic series. This capstone volume addresses central topics in the history of logic, showing how logicians, philosophers, mathematicians and others understood these topics over the years and how they guided their development down to the present century.

    Certainly the most central topic in logic is the notion of logical consequence. Asmus and Restall start with Aristotles definition of a syllogism as an argument in which, certain things having been assumed, something other than these follows of necessity from their truth, without needing any term from outside and carry the explanation of this conception through the middle ages and into the twenty-first century. Any account of logical consequence must determine the type of entities that can be premises and conclusion, must explain what ways premises can combine, and crucially, must explain the types of connection that that are allowed to hold between premises and conclusion in order for it to really be a consequence.

    A part of this explanation will involve certain connected concepts: the quantifiers and the connectives. Bonevac traces the notion of quantification from Aristotle through modern generalized quantifiers. It is important to note, he says, that there is no theory-neutral way of defining quantification or even of delineating the class of quantifiers, and so a history of quantification has to trace the development of both what is to be explained along with how it is to be explained. Alongside the account of quantifiers and quantification needs to be an account of the logical particles the connectives. Bonevac and Dever discuss the implicit treatment of propositional connectives in Aristotle before moving on to the explicit theory of them developed by the Stoics. The development of an understanding of the connectives took a winding path from the Stoics through the medieval logica vetus (Old Logic) and the revolutionary logica nova (New Logic) of the 13th century, through the under-appreciated algebraic understanding of Leibniz, and to the Modern-Era logicians of the 19th and 20th century.

    As Bonevac and Dever remark, the history of the connectives is marked by an ambivalence between the attitude that the connectives are operators on the content of the items being connected and an attitude that they are operators on the speech-act force of the items (say, in a presentation of an argument). And again, there is the ambivalence between the view that negation is a propositional operator (It is not the case that -) and that it is a term operator (- is notpale). The 20th century saw the latter issue decided in favor of the propositional approach for negation. However, the question of whether negation is a content or a speech-act operator (for instance, denial) is disputed. Speranza and Horn start with Paul Grices account of negation, using it as a springboard to discuss the ways this difference has been in effect over the history of logic.

    Aristotles notion of following of necessity from the truth of the premises is often described in terms of the truth-values of the premises and the conclusion: It is not possible for the truth-value of every premise to be true while the truth-value of the conclusion is false. But of course, the history of logic has seen accounts where there are more than two truth-values, and furthermore where there are gaps and gluts of truth-value. Indeed, the notion of truth-value permeates much of the broader realms of philosophy, linguistics, mathematics and computer science, and Beziau undertakes a very broad-ranging discussion of the mathematical conception of truth-value to show how it underlies many of the more familiar conceptions that are associated with that concept.

    Modality is yet another central concept in logic. Not only is it employed in Aristotles definition of a correct argument, but also it features in the characterization of modalized sentences, and thereby into metaphysics and language (de re and de dicto modalities). Knuuttila explores the ancient and medieval traditions in modality distinguishing modality as extensional (all possibilities will be actualized) from modality as alternativity and showing where these two conceptions emerge in more recent accounts of modality. These differing accounts also are manifested in the modal syllogistic and logics that were developed in ancient and medieval times, Knuuttila shows, as were interpretations of the modalities in terms of epistemic operators like knows and believes.

    One version of logic employs no independently-claimed-to-be-necessarily-true statements (axioms) but instead employs only rules. Although some have claimed that Aristotles syllogistic is such a system, the more modern version traces its history to 1934. Despite this very recent invention, most logic that is currently taught in philosophy is of this nature natural deduction. Pelletier and Hazen discuss the history (since 1934) of this development, its relationship with other conceptions of logic, and the metatheoretic facts that allow it to have such a prominent position in modern logic.

    Next page
    Light

    Font size:

    Reset

    Interval:

    Bookmark:

    Make

    Similar books «Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts»

    Look at similar books to Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


    Reviews about «Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts»

    Discussion, reviews of the book Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 11, Logic, a history of its central concepts and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.