The contents of this book are based upon a filmed conversation between Howard Burton and Onora ONeill in London, England, on October 3, 2016.
Introduction
The Benefits of Struggling
Immanuel Kant is not the easiest philosopher to read.
To start with, he is German, which not only makes him notoriously hard to grapple with for many of those who dont speak German as a native language, but is surprisingly troublesome even for those who do, with many German scholars rather bizarrely opting to ponder his ideas in English.
Then there is the fact that Kant was known to be a particularly formal and scrupulous thinker even by 18th-century Prussian standardswhich is indeed saying somethinga philosopher who prized our capacity for reason above all else, developing a highly systematic and abstract interpretation of how we come to know and have confidence in the world around us through the medium of our human minds and associated categories of understanding.
But Kantrigorous, all-encompassing sort that he wasdidnt limit himself to matters of metaphysics and epistemology. He also had a great deal to say about ethics and morality in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, which has the dubious reputation of being particularly challenging to penetrate even by Kantian standardswhich, as youve doubtless recognized by now, is truly saying something.
The celebrated moral philosopher and Kantian scholar Onora ONeill remembers that her own path to Kant was hardly straightforward. As a young graduate student she was initially intrigued by the extremely fashionable rational choice models that surrounded her before eventually becoming convinced of its fundamental implausibility.
I didnt feel that it gave one any insight into good reasons for doing anything. To say, I prefer X, or I like X is not a very good reason for doing X. It might be a good reason in certain circumstances with lots of other stuff put in there.
So the idea that preferences and desires have either normative or explanatory force seems to me a bit over the top, although theyre widely taken to have that sort of force of weight.
What she was looking for, was some clear structuresome straightforward, objective, defensive way of being able to determine what should be done in a given situation. That brought her, naturally enough, to Kantbut not straight away.
The detour I took before I started reading Kant seriously during my second or third year as a graduate student, was a detour to look at people who were trying to use certain formal constraints on top of utilitarianism, although their utilitarianism was muted and masked.
It was the formalism that attracted me. I suppose the fundamental intuition is: If you can get places with minimal assumptions, thats much more valuable than getting places on the back of extravagant assumptions. And that parsimony in premises is what I thought I was going to find in looking at some of these 20th-century writerspeople like Marcus Singer and Kurt Baier.
Eventually, appropriately enough, she discarded the vestiges of utilitarianism injected by later thinkers and recognized that what she was looking for was clearly delineated by Kant himself.
Kant is different. The categorical imperative combines two aspects of what is loosely called universalism.
One is the idea that principles have the form of law: they cover all cases in a certain domain. So whether it is Thou shalt not bear false witness or Remember to renew your subscription at the end of the month, it is universal in formits addressed to anybody.
But what is interesting about the categorical imperative is that Kant is also asking whether it is universal in scope. And thats a different matter, because universal in scope means that it is a principle for anybody and everybody. So, Renew your subscription at the beginning of the month does not have universal scopeit will only apply to people whose subscription falls due this month, et cetera.
Kant is putting forward both a formal criterion and a scope criterion. Hes saying, Principles that do not meet both are not fit to be universal laws and should be rejected.
Well, you might think, I can see how using such a decision procedure can be profitably used to guide my individual moral behaviour, but surely it doesnt have many implications in terms of my relationships with others throughout society.
But youd be wrong. Because the universality that Kant places so much stress on, naturally implies a high level of direct interaction, potential or actual, with our fellow human beings.
Kant thinks that the key is to realize that theres a plurality of agents. Otherwise, what would this universality be for? Its got to be able to reach, not just those of a particular sentiment or particular outlook, but just anybody.
Kant thinks of reason, or reasoning, in a transactional way: I give someone a reason; he accepts or rejects the reason and gives me a reason in return.
From there you can get to the thought, Well, whatever were giving has to be accessible to both of us, it has to be followable to both partiesor if youre talking about a lot of people: all parties.
And it is that idea that a principle has to be followable in thoughtif its a theoretical ideaor adoptable for actionif its a practical principlethat I think Kant is saying.
And suddenly, this old, fusty, highly formal Prussian who was reputed to be so regular in his habits that the inhabitants of Knigsberg set their watches by when he passed certain city landmarks on his daily stroll, becomes a hugely valuable motivating force to help us better grapple with a wide variety of thorny issues in our contemporary social world, from minority rights to patient consent to corporate transparencyall of which, and a good deal more besides, Onora has passionately engaged in, to societys untold benefit.
Sometimes difficult prose is very much worth the effort.
The Conversation
I. A Circuitous Route
Philosophy via history, psychology and physiology
HB: Id like to begin, as I invariably do, at the beginning, exploring your origins and intellectual motivations. The story that I read was that you had enrolled as an undergraduate in history and French