• Complain

Daniel S. Milo - Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society

Here you can read online Daniel S. Milo - Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2019, publisher: Harvard University Press, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover
  • Book:
    Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Harvard University Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2019
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

In this spirited and irreverent critique of Darwins long hold over our imagination, a distinguished philosopher of science makes the case that, in culture as well as nature, not only the fittest survive: the world is full of the good enough that persist too.
Why is the genome of a salamander forty times larger than that of a human? Why does the avocado tree produce a million flowers and only a hundred fruits? Why, in short, is there so much waste in nature? In this lively and wide-ranging meditation on the curious accidents and unexpected detours on the path of life, Daniel Milo argues that we ask these questions because weve embraced a faulty conception of how evolution--and human society--really works.
Good Enoughoffers a vigorous critique of the quasi-monopoly that Darwins concept of natural selection has on our idea of the natural world. Darwinism excels in accounting for the evolution of traits, but it does not explain their excess in size and number. Many traits far exceed the optimal configuration to do the job, and yet the maintenance of this extra baggage does not prevent species from thriving for millions of years. Milo aims to give the messy side of nature its due--to stand up for the wasteful and inefficient organisms that nevertheless survive and multiply.
But he does not stop at the border between evolutionary theory and its social consequences. He argues provocatively that the theory of evolution through natural selection has acquired the trappings of an ethical system. Optimization, competitiveness, and innovation have become the watchwords of Western societies, yet their role in human lives--as in the rest of nature--is dangerously overrated. Imperfection is not just good enough: it may at times be essential to survival.

Daniel S. Milo: author's other books


Who wrote Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Contents
Guide
Pagebreaks of the print version
good enough The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society DANIEL S MILO - photo 1

good enough

The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society

DANIEL S. MILO

Cambridge Massachusetts London England 2019 Copyright 2019 by the President - photo 2Picture 3

Cambridge, Massachusetts

London, England

2019

Copyright 2019 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College

All rights reserved

Cover image: Giraffe/Private Collection/Bridgeman Images

Cover design: Jill Breitbarth

978-0-674-50462-2 (alk. paper)

978-0-674-24005-6 (EPUB)

978-0-674-24006-3 (MOBI)

978-0-674-24004-9 (PDF)

The Library of Congress has cataloged the printed edition as follows:

Names: Milo, Daniel S. (Daniel Shabeta), author.

Title: Good enough : the tolerance for mediocrity in nature and society /

Daniel S. Milo.

Description: Cambridge, Massachusetts : Harvard University Press, 2019. |

Includes bibliographical references and index.

Identifiers: LCCN 2018052620

Subjects: LCSH: Evolution (Biology) | Natural selection. | Social evolution. |

Imperfection.

Classification: LCC QH366.2 .M555 2019 | DDC 576.8dc23

LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2018052620

In memory of my beloved,

Naomi Aviv Milo,

who knew

Contents

The world of things living has room, wide but not unbounded, for variety of living form and structure, as these tend towards their seemingly endless but yet strictly limited possibilities of permutation and degree: it has room for the great and for the small, room for the weak and for the strong The ways of life may be changed, and many a refuge found, before the sentence of unfitness is pronounced and the penalty of extermination paid.

DArcy Wentworth Thompson, On Growth and Form (1942)

Sigmund Freud wrote of three successive scientific outrages upon [humanitys] naive self-love. The first was inaugurated by Copernicus, who discovered that our earth was not the center of the universe, but only a tiny speck in a world-system of a magnitude hardly conceivable. The last was Freuds own: the revelation to the ego of each one of us that he is not even master in his own house. Between them was an idea that arrived upon the instigation of Charles Darwin, [Alfred Russel] Wallace, and their predecessors. This was the evolution of species by means of natural selection, which robbed man of his peculiar privilege of having been specially created, and relegated him to a descent from the animal world, implying an ineradicable animal nature in him.

The repercussions of two of those outrages were far-reaching. While the Copernican revolution resists popular appropriationperhaps because we are not capable of experiencing the earth as other than flat and the sun as other than rising and settingevolution and psychoanalysis mold our worldview. This despite the fact that few of us have opened The Interpretation of Dreams, and even professional biologists rarely read On the Origin of Species. Freuds key conceptssubconscious; Oedipal complex; libido; reality and pleasure principles; defense mechanisms; sublimation; narcissism; id, ego, and superegoare embedded in daily life no less than in therapeutic practice. Darwinism is similarly inescapable. Natural selection, struggle for survival, Malthusian competition, humanitys apish origin, and adaptation are all pervasive in thinking about nature and human communities.

In particular, Darwinism courses through the ethics of capitalism. The latters termsmaximization, optimization, competitiveness, innovation, efficiency, cost-benefit trade-offs, rationalizationdraw on the authority of Darwinian views of nature. Social Darwinism may be pass, but natural capitalism is fully alive. In the pages that follow, I will argue that Darwinism and neo-Darwinismthe mating of natural selection and genetics established in the mid-twentieth centuryhave a lot in common with neoliberalism. Nature knows what she is doing; in the market we trust. Homo economicus and animal economicus pursue the same goals and obey the same rules.

If evolutionary thought all too easily naturalizes capitalisms competitive zeal, it is because Darwin was only partly right. There is no doubt that all organisms evolved from a common ancestor. But Darwin strayed in attributing evolution overwhelmingly to natural selection. It is this view that inspired Herbert Spencer, the father of social Darwinism, to coin survival of the fittest. At Wallaces suggestion, Darwin himself eventually adopted this concept, too. It remains the basis of popular understanding of evolution today: everyone knows that nature is harsh and only the strong survive. But they are only partly right: nature is harsh sometimes; the strong survive often, but the weak stand a chance, too.

Both experts and the public join Darwin in overemphasizing natural selection, thereby distorting our sense of its role in both nature and humanity. Natural selection does occur, but there are nonadaptive mechanisms of change as well, such as genetic drift, geographic isolation, and the founder effect. None of these paths to survival rewards the hardest struggler or the best specimen. Their rewards are governed not by merit but by chance.

Genetic drift, the most prominent of these mechanisms, is the random change in the relative frequency of a gene variant, or allele, within a population. Genetic drift results in the survival not of the fittest but of the luckiest. One example is the northern elephant seal (Mirounga angustirostris). This seal experienced what evolutionary biologists call a bottleneck: an abrupt and drastic reduction in population size due to an environmental shock. By the late nineteenth century, the northern elephant seal had been harvested nearly to extinction for the oil derived from its blubber. Just a hundred or so specimens from Guadalupe Island, off Baja California, survived under the protection of the Mexican government. Those seals alleles persist in todays population not because they were selected but because they got lucky.

Geographic isolation occurs when a population is cut off from the other members of its species. It can lead to speciation by means of inbreeding within a narrowed gene pool. The isolated population has only so many variants in it, and only these can be passed down and recombined in the next generation. The result is divergence from the original population, as each is now reproducing a different set of alleles. The origin of the new species is not natural selection but chance.

Likewise, the founder effect occurs when a few members of a population strike out from their habitat and start a new community. But though these founders may initiate an enduring lineage, they are not necessarily the fittest of their kind, nor do they necessarily adapt to their new environments through the fixation of advantageous mutations. A famous example is the small group of pigeons that landed on the island of Mauritius ages ago, lost their ability to fly, gained twenty kilograms, and evolved into Raphus cucullatus, also known as the dodo. The origin of this species was due to chance.

Specialists understand all this, so they avoid using survival of the fittest. And they know that natural selection does not cull every useless, exaggerated, and inefficient mutation, preserving only the best. Yet in 2007, Richard Dawkins defended the image of nature as a miserly

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society»

Look at similar books to Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society»

Discussion, reviews of the book Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.