• Complain

Sam Mitchell - Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification

Here you can read online Sam Mitchell - Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2020, publisher: De Gruyter, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

No cover
  • Book:
    Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    De Gruyter
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2020
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

It is widely believed in philosophy of science that nobody can claim that any verdict of science is forced upon us by the effects of a physical world upon our sense organs and instruments. The Quine-Duhem problem supposedly allows us to resist any conclusion. Views on language aside, Quine is supposed to have shown this decisively.

But it is just false. In many scientific examples, there is simply no room to doubt that a particular hypothesis is responsible for a refutation or established by the observations.

Fault Tracing shows how to play independently established hypotheses against each other to determine whether an arbitrary hypothesis needs to be altered in the light of (apparently) refuting evidence. It analyses real examples from natural science, as well as simpler cases. It argues that, when scientific theories have a structure that prevents them from using this method, the theory looks wrong, and is subject to serious criticism. This is a new, and potentially far-reaching, theory of empirical justification.

Sam Mitchell: author's other books


Who wrote Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Epistemic Studies Philosophy of Science Cognition and Mind Edited by Michael - photo 1

Epistemic Studies

Philosophy of Science, Cognition and Mind

Edited by

Michael Esfeld
Stephan Hartmann
Albert Newen
Katalin Balog
Claus Beisbart
Craig Callender
Tim Crane
Katja Crone
Ophelia Deroy
Mauro Dorato
Alison Fernandes
Jens Harbecke
Vera Hoffmann-Kolss
Max Kistler
Beate Krickel
Anna Marmodoro
Alyssa Ney
Hans Rott
Wolfgang Spohn
Gottfried Vosgerau

Volume

ISBN 9783110684995

e-ISBN (PDF) 9783110685046

e-ISBN (EPUB) 9783110685091

Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek

The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de.

2020 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Introduction
The Quine-Duhem hypothesis

To anyone even slightly acquainted with the history of philosophy since 1950, the view defended in this book must seem utterly untenable. It argues against the position on sciences that W. V. O. Quine, drawing upon the work of Pierre Duhem, so decisively championed in the mid-twentieth century. The upshot of the debate was a decisive victory for the Quine-Duhem hypothesis the view that no matter what outcomes we have observed at any time, thepractice of science cannot use only those outcomes to select whether to give up or to adopt some given hypothesis. We may believe in spite of an apparent refutation, by blaming some other hypothesis instead. By contrast, this book argues that the outcomes of observation sometimes do not permit us any choice in deciding which hypotheses are at fault when we observe something that our former beliefs prohibited.

An academic book should be an attempt to make a move in the way we now think about some subject. It must begin with the position in that subject as it is widely perceived at present before it attempts to move forward. This book, then, is aimed at a readership that is familiar with views on confirmation in the philosophy of science.

I do not want to go back to the battles of the 1950s and 1960s. The literature is unmanageably massive and framed in ways that are now dated. Revisiting it will not change anyones mind. That literature is almost exclusively concerned with Quines first dogma the analytic/synthetic distinction. That focus continues even up to the present day ().

This book, by contrast, looks closely at Quines second dogma, namely that hypotheses of a scientific theory face observations not individually, but only as a collective group. This hypothesis has been much more widely seen as true and has had a huge influence (although Clark Glymour did politely demure to some extent (1980)). In the sense in which it is true, I will argue, the Quine-Duhem hypothesis does not follow from it. It has, moreover, had pernicious effects. It has yielded a poor analysis of justification as it occurs within natural science.

What is the argument for Quine-Duhem? The second dogma says that we may compensate for the future outcomes of observation, not by altering our view of the justification for that given hypothesis, but rather by adapting our view on the justification of other hypotheses we believe.

Quine then presented a dilemma:

  1. Either empirical justifications depend upon auxiliaries, which must in turn be justified, to give a circle or endless sequence, or not.

  2. If empirical justifications do ramify endlessly, or cycle, then the Quine-Duhem hypothesis is true.

  3. If they dont, then some version of foundationalism is true.

  4. Foundationalism is hopeless.

  5. So the Quine-Duhem hypothesis is true.

This book shows that 3 is false. The chains of justification for a succession of auxiliaries can come to an end, in a finite time, without precipitating us into any version of foundationalism. Observation can be as theory-laden as you like. We can keep the examples of shifting blame to auxiliaries that we find in the history of science or our own reasoning. Empirical results are indeed widely interconnected; observations of X-ray diffraction do have consequences for hypotheses about the lift generated by the wing of a bird. The sense-data theory of perception can be utterly hopeless. We can be as anti-reductionist as we like. We can gain the advances for which Quine argued the rejection of foundationalism and the sensitivity to auxiliary hypotheses without surrendering to the pragmatist view of science that he so vividly presented in the last section of Two Dogmas of Empiricism ( (1980)). We can successfully practice and reason about the science we in fact possess without the Quine-Duhem hypothesis. We can be empiricists. That is the view that seems utterly untenable but which this book defends.

I call this alternative to the Quine-Duhem hypothesis constructivism because there is a clear intuitive sense in which the justification for a hypothesis is constructed from outcomes of observation. In nearly every case, a justification uses auxiliary hypotheses, and these must be confirmed independently of the target hypothesis. The process must terminate in hypotheses that are justified from the outcomes of observation without using additional auxiliaries. The word constructive is intended to be analogous to a constructive proof in logic or mathematics. Constructivism in the philosophy of science has close connections to intuitionism in the philosophy of mathematics (). The clearest descriptive title for the view would be empiricist constructivism, but that is much too close to van Fraassens constructive empiricism (1980, 1989). Unlike constructive empiricism, constructivism holds that hypotheses concerning unobservable entities are justified by the outcomes of observation in the same way as hypotheses concerning observable entities.

, 43) wrote:

Any statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system.

This is the Quine-Duhem hypothesis. The view occurs elsewhere. Two influential statements of it are:

The physicist can never subject an isolated hypothesis to experimental test, but only a whole group of hypotheses; when the experiment is in disagreement with his predictions, what he learns is that at least one of the hypotheses is unacceptable but the experiment does not designate which one should be changed.

(, 187, see also 185)

In principle, it would always be possible to retain [a hypothesis] even in the face of seriously adverse test results providing we are willing to make sufficiently radical and perhaps burdensome revisions among our auxiliary hypotheses.

(Hempel 1964, 28).

This viewpoint has been endlessly repeated up until the present day, like an incantation in a dead tongue. What follows is a sample, which I do not claim to be exhaustive: , 36), but we keep believing it, or saying that we do.

The Quine-Duhem hypothesis is important for the broader topic of epistemology, not just for the philosophy of science. Still, it is important that it should be answered from within the philosophy of natural science. That is where the argument was first proposed and argued. Duhem was a philosopher of science, and made his case from within that discipline. Quine was explicitly thinking in terms of natural science. Besides providing the arguments that first supported the Quine-Duhem hypothesis, natural science ought to play a particularly influential role in epistemology more generally. It provides a rich store of detailed and explicit examples of

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification»

Look at similar books to Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification»

Discussion, reviews of the book Fault-Tracing: Against Quine-Duhem: A Defense of the Objectivity of Scientific Justification and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.