• Complain

Agassi - Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos

Here you can read online Agassi - Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2014, publisher: Springer, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Agassi Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos
  • Book:
    Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Springer
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2014
  • Rating:
    5 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 100
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

This volume examines Poppers philosophyby analyzingthe criticismofhis most popular critics:Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos. They all followedhisrejection of the traditional view of science as inductive. Starting from the assumption that Humes criticism of induction is valid, the book explores the central criticism and objections that these three critics have raised.Their objections have met with great success, are significant and deserve paraphrase. One alsomay consider them reasonable protests against Poppers high standards rather thanfundamental criticisms of his philosophy.The book starts out with a preliminary discussion of some central background material and essentials of Poppers philosophy. It ends with nutshell representations of the philosophies of Popper. Kuhn, Feyerabend and Lakatos. The middle section of the book presents the connection between these philosophers and explains what their central ideas consists of, what the critical arguments are, how they presented them, and how valid they are. In the process, the author claims that Poppers popular critics used against him arguments that he had invented (and answered) without saying so. They differ from him mainly in that they demanded of all criticism that it should be constructive: do not stop believing a refuted theory unless there is a better alternative to it. Popper hardly ever discussed belief, delegating its study to psychology proper; he usually discussed only objective knowledge, knowledge that is public and thus open to public scrutiny. Read more...
Abstract: This volume examines Poppers philosophyby analyzingthe criticismofhis most popular critics:Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos. They all followedhisrejection of the traditional view of science as inductive. Starting from the assumption that Humes criticism of induction is valid, the book explores the central criticism and objections that these three critics have raised.Their objections have met with great success, are significant and deserve paraphrase. One alsomay consider them reasonable protests against Poppers high standards rather thanfundamental criticisms of his philosophy.The book starts out with a preliminary discussion of some central background material and essentials of Poppers philosophy. It ends with nutshell representations of the philosophies of Popper. Kuhn, Feyerabend and Lakatos. The middle section of the book presents the connection between these philosophers and explains what their central ideas consists of, what the critical arguments are, how they presented them, and how valid they are. In the process, the author claims that Poppers popular critics used against him arguments that he had invented (and answered) without saying so. They differ from him mainly in that they demanded of all criticism that it should be constructive: do not stop believing a refuted theory unless there is a better alternative to it. Popper hardly ever discussed belief, delegating its study to psychology proper; he usually discussed only objective knowledge, knowledge that is public and thus open to public scrutiny

Agassi: author's other books


Who wrote Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Part 1
Prelims
Joseph Agassi SpringerBriefs in Philosophy Popper and His Popular Critics 2014 Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos 10.1007/978-3-319-06587-8_1
The Author(s) 2014
1. On Human Rules About Gods World
Joseph Agassi 1
(1)
Tel Aviv University, 69978 Tel Aviv, Israel
Joseph Agassi
Email:
Abstract
The story El Aleph of Jorge Luis Borges concerns the rules of art: are its rules after the facts? Are some rules helpful? Are there some absolute rules? Can the best system of science possibly contain an image of the whole cosmos? Borges adopted Russells answer: the cosmos is too rich for that. Popper and Polanyi agreed. Kuhn followed Polanyi; Feyerabend followed Popper. A posthumous book of his is Conquest of Abundance: A Tale of Abstraction versus the Richness of Being .
The short story El Aleph of Jorge Luis Borges concerns aestheticshow the rules of art relate to superior poetry (or to superior art in general; it is hard to judge). On the spur of the moment, Borges suggests, poor poets make up rules to justify whatever goes into their artto no avail. To be good, art must be kaleidoscopic: it must present its object in diverse perspectives and thereby reflect the whole world, no less, and in many ways. Borges envisioned a materialization of this kaleidoscope; he named it an alephafter the first letter of the first alphabet, the numerological name for the First, the kabalistic name for the origins of the universe; the name that arch-mathematician Georg Cantor gave actual infinity.
Borges wrote prose and poetry. His prose excels; hardly his poetry. His prose pieces are concise sketches, outlines of veiled secrets, barely told tales, and abstracts of philosophical treatises. One of these, Borges and I, is (a prcis of) a fabulous essay of less than one page that reports about two selves of his, one humble one vain. He confesses there ignorance as to who is more real. His ascription of vanity to himself is possibly an expression of his fear that since the quality of his poetry is not the highest, his publication of it rested on vanity. We may then read his confessed ignorance here as a silent prayer that the esteem for his poetry will rise.
The plot summary of El Aleph is this. The deceased sweetheart of the narrator had lived in one house with a relative of hers who is an inept poet working on an ambitious project of writing a poem about everything while making up rules to justify his poor choice of words. The narrator befriends him in order to frequent the home of his deceased sweetheart. One day the relative sees an aleph in his cellar. He fears losing his mind. The narrator volunteers to verify the strange fact. Down in the cellar he feasts his eyes on the marvel. Upon his return, the inept poet asks him anxiously: did you see it? No, he replies cruelly. Later the inept poet gains honors, moves to a better house and demolishes his old one. The narrator reports about another manifestation of the aleph.
This expresses obliquely Borges fears that his poems are poor (and of his having published them as vain) as his painful awareness of his ability to see but not to articulate his vision. The story must have more readings: it is kaleidoscopiclike all of Borges prose that is poetic.
The storys center is the contrast between the poor artist who makes rules after the facts and the inexhaustible richness of existence. Are all rules after the facts? Are some rules helpful? Borges raises these questions regarding art. Others did so regarding evolutionary and developmental psychology, learning and education theory, generative grammar and philosophy, learning and research: can the best system of science possibly contain an image of the whole cosmos? Russell said (1914), of course not. Popper and Polanyi agreed: the cosmos is too rich for that. Kuhn followed Polanyi; Feyerabend followed Popper. A posthumous book of his is Conquest of Abundance: A Tale of Abstraction versus the Richness of Being. As science is limited, does it nonetheless reflect reality? How?
The Age of Reason replaced traditional religious skepticism and took it for granted that science can encompass Gods world. Even then some of the greatest thinkers doubted that, particularly David Hume and Immanuel Kant. In the middle of the nineteenth century William Whewell challenged traditional views about the rules of scientific research to make room for creativity. At the turn of the nineteenth century Pierre Duhem did the same more radically to allow freedom in research. Soon Popper developed the ideacritical rationalismthat the rules for scientific research do not depend on the world. To insure that this was the case he chose the smallest subset possible of the traditional set of rules for research: suffice it for scientific theories that they should be open to empirical criticism. This fits with Einsteins view: research is putting questions to Nature; She can say no and She can say maybe; She never says yes. The standard objection to Popper is naturally that his set of rules is too poor. Other oppositions were that we cannot articulate the rules (Kuhn), that there are no rules (Feyerabend) or that we need new rules (Lakatos).
Borges plays here the terrific role of bridging between traditional religious skepticism and the modern view of reason that is more humble than that of the Age of Reason but is rationalist all the same. This way he began the project dear to the heart of Feyerabendof bridging between the arts and the sciences. Borges shunned capricious whims; as he has put it, he preferred naturalistic explanations to mystic ones. His naturalism is remarkably realist:
If I could live again my life,
In the nextIll try,
to make more mistakes,
I wont try to be so
perfect, Ill be more
relaxed
Ill take fewer things seriously
Ill take more risks
Bibliography
Agassi, Joseph. 1998. Science real and ideal: Popper and the dogmatic scientist. Protosociology 12: 297304.
Borges, Jorge Luis. 1964. Labyrinths: Selected stories and other writings .
Feyerabend, Paul. 1967. On the Improvement of the Sciences and the Arts and the Possible Identity of the Two, Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science , 387415, 19641966.
Feyerabend, Paul. 1999. Conquest of abundance: A tale of abstraction versus the richness of being .
Fuller, Steve. 1989. Philosophy of science and its discontent .
Holton, Gerald. 1974. On being caught between dionysians and apollonians. Daedalus 103: 6581.
Kuhn, T.S. 1962, 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions .
Laktos, Imre. 1978. The methodology of scientific research programmes .
Polanyi, Michael. 1962. The republic of science. Minerva , 1: 5473.
Popper, K.R. 1983. Realism and the aim of science .
Ziman, John. 1968. Public knowledge: An essay concerning the social dimension of science .
Joseph Agassi SpringerBriefs in Philosophy Popper and His Popular Critics 2014 Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos 10.1007/978-3-319-06587-8_2
The Author(s) 2014
2. In Search for Rules
Joseph Agassi 1
(1)
Tel Aviv University, 69978 Tel Aviv, Israel
Joseph Agassi
Email:
Abstract
How is navigation possible between dogmatism and relativism? Traditionally, the chief aims of the rules were first to prevent error and second to reveal the truth. This is an excess. Fallibilism tries to rectify the situation. The central problem that Fallibilism raises is, what error is allowable, reasonable, or even fruitful? Philosophers of science deem science a success story and seek rules for total success. Feyerabend exposed this as a serious error, defending the freedom of speech that includes the freedom to assert foolish ideas. He offered this as a critique of the idea of rationality. It is but the view that rationality is not legally obligatory. It still is advisable.
Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos»

Look at similar books to Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos»

Discussion, reviews of the book Popper and his popular critics : Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.