• Complain

Solomon Robert Charles - Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon

Here you can read online Solomon Robert Charles - Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. City: New York, Dordrecht, year: 2012, publisher: Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Solomon Robert Charles Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon

Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

Robert C. Solomon, who died in 2007, was Professor of Philosophy and Quincy Lee Centennial Professor of Business at the University of Texas, USA. As the first book comprehensively to examine the breadth of Solomon, s contribution to philosophy, this volume ranks as a vital addition to the literature. It includes a newly published transcript of Solomon, s last talk, which responded to Arindam Chakrabarti on the concept of revenge, as well as the considered views of prominent figures in the numerous subfields in which Solomon worked. The content analyses his perspectives on the philosophy of emoti. Read more...
Abstract: This book examines the breadth of Robert C. Solomons contribution to philosophy, surveying the themes of passion, ethics and spirituality which threaded through his work, and the way these ideas informed his views on how we should approach grief and death. Read more...

Solomon Robert Charles: author's other books


Who wrote Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Part 1
EMOTIONS
Kathleen Higgins and David Sherman (eds.) Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures Passion, Death, and Spirituality 2012 The Philosophy of Robert C. Solomon 10.1007/978-94-007-4650-3_1 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012
1. Sensational Judgmentalism: Reconciling Solomon and James
Jesse J. Prinz 1
(1)
Department of Philosophy, CUNY Graduate Center, City University of New York, 365 5th Avenue, New York, NY 10016, USA
Jesse J. Prinz
Email:
Abstract
Robert Solomon is responsible for developing one of the most influential and sophisticated cognitive theories of emotion in recent philosophy. In his own work, and in commentaries, this theory is often contrasted with the non-cognitive theory of William James. For James, emotions are felt sensations of changes in the body. For Solomon, emotions are judgments that have intentional objects and can occur without feelings. Solomon also says that emotions, unlike usual sensations, are strategic choices rather than automatics responses. This chapter argues that, despite this apparent contrast, the Jamesian view can be adapted to satisfy the basic tenets of Solomons theory, and the resulting hybrid may have been anticipated in Solomon, despite his reservations about James.
No one contributed more to contemporary philosophical discussions of emotion that Bob Solomon. His seminal work in the 1970s helped set the agenda for decades to come, and the arguments he offered in those early works remain as relevant today as they were when they were originally penned. Those of us who came to this discussion in recent years revere Solomon as an intellectual hero. But many of us have also used him as a foil. As so often happens in academe, newcomers try to kill the father, and often then resurrect the grandfather as an alternative. In this case, the grandfather is William James. The last two decades have witnessed a Jamesian turn in emotion theory, and Solomons views are often seen as the polar opposite. Solomon authored some of the most penetrating critiques of the Jamesian approach, and his positive theory of the emotions often looks like a systematic inversion of Jamess core tenets. As a Jamesian, this is how Id seen things, and despite receiving unbelievably gracious support and encouragement from Solomon during my early forays, Id thought of his work as more of a foil than a foundation. I realize now that this was a mistake. Many of Solomons most controversial views strike me as plausible now, not because James was wrong, but because there is room for a reconciliation. Solomon was a leading force in bringing together different disciplines (psychology, anthropology, and philosophy), different generations (historical and contemporary sources of influence), and different philosophical traditions (analytic and continental). It turns out that he was also prescient in seeing how the most ostensibly antithetical theories of emotion might find some common ground. This is the most important of many philosophical lessons I learned from him, not only because it is crucial for understanding emotions, but because it serves as a reminder, in this polarizing field, that the best solution to many of our debates is collaboration.
In what follows, I begin by presenting some of the central themes in Solomons theory of the emotions, focusing on his groundbreaking 1973 paper, but updating where appropriate. I indicate how these themes depart from the position advanced by James. Then, in the second part, I argue that the Jamesian should not reject Solomons arguments, but rather accommodate them, and I will suggest that his considered view can be regarded as integrative as well.
Solomon Contra James
In , James published his first and most influential discussion of the emotions. There he defends a view that is sometimes called sensationalism . According to James, emotions are felt sensations of changes that take place in the body. When we experience an emotionally evocative event, our bodies prepare for a behavioral response, and the feeling of those preparations is the emotion. When we encounter a bear in the wilderness, to use a Jamesian paradigm case, our bodies prepare for flight, our hearts race, we perspire, and we get goose bumps (a vestige from hairier ancestors whose goose bumps caused hair to erect, giving rise to a larger appearance in the eyes of predators). The emotion of fear is a sensation comprising this somatic pattern.
James based this account on two central observations. The first is phenomenological. James asks readers to imagine an intense emotion, such as rage or terror, and then systematically subtract in our minds all its bodily symptoms. If we try this exercise, James says, we will find that there is nothing left that we would recognize as an emotion. The phenomenology of emotion is fundamentally bodily. The second observation is more or less empiricalit was speculative in Jamess time but has since been tested and confirmed. When we change the configuration of our bodies, our emotions seem to change as well. James combated his own depression by adopting an erect posture and a smile, methods known now to enhance mood. If bodily changes can change our emotions, then, James concludes, emotions may be sensations of such changes. These arguments continue to persuade some contemporary emotion researchers and have been buffered by empirical work linking emotional responses to brain structures that are involved in the perception of bodily changes (Damasio ).
Jamess theory of the emotions captivated philosophers and psychologists when it first appeared, and it became a dominant theory until 40 years later, when Walter Cannon () endorses this critique, which has often received inadequate attention by contemporary followers of James.
It should be noted, however, that the critique is less decisive than it may appear. First, some forms of bodily perception, such as heart rate, can be quite accurate and fast. Second, the fact that some visceral nerves are slow does not undermine the Jamesian theory, because emotions sometimes come on slowly, and because emotional experiences may begin as soon as the brain anticipates changes in the body, even if such changes have not yet taken place or been perceived. Third, the fact that stimulating an organ does not cause an emotional sensation can be explained by the fact that emotions involve whole patterns of bodily change. The stimulation of one organ alone would not suffice. This also speaks to the questions of differentiation. A rapid heart rate would not be enough to distinguish fear and euphoria, since both involve cardiovascular acceleration. But fear also characteristically involves a muscle tension (part of the freezing response), widened eyes, and tingling spine. And euphoria causes flushing rather than pallor, and the lips turn upward rather than down. Inducing such global patterns of change can indeed cause felt changes in the emotions. Indeed, facial expressions (Laird ) may be enough to differentiate basic emotions. So the case against James cannot hang on Cannons critique. Solomon certainly wouldnt make this mistake. His central objections to James have little to do with physiology. Rather, he defends a positive theory of his own, which seems to conflict with sensationalism in multiple ways.
Solomons approach to the emotions is inspired by Sartre rather than James. His overarching claim is that emotions are judgments, not sensations. James is a non-cognitivist. That is, he thinks cognitive states are unnecessary for emotions. An emotion can be triggered by a perceptual experience (seeing a bear), and consist in somatic sensations. A creature without thoughts could emote. For Solomon, emotions are fundamentally cognitive: they are judgments about states of affairs in the world, such as the judgment that the bear is dangerous. This can be called judgmentalism . Like James, Solomon cites phenomenological evidence. His paradigm case is anger, which he associates with the judgment that there has been an offense. He invites us to imagine being angry with no such judgment, and concludes that this impossible. It would be paradoxical, in a Moorian way, to say, I am angry at you, but I dont think youve done anything wrong.
Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon»

Look at similar books to Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon»

Discussion, reviews of the book Passion, death, and spirituality : the philosophy of Robert C. Solomon and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.