• Complain

Robert J. Roecklein - Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought

Here you can read online Robert J. Roecklein - Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2012, publisher: Lexington Books, genre: Science / Politics. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Robert J. Roecklein Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought
  • Book:
    Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Lexington Books
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2012
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

This book investigates the influence of Epicurean physics on the argument developed in Machiavellis Discourses on Livy. Towards this end, the full philosophical history and origins of atomist philosophy are investigated during the first three chapters. Platos critique of the atomist philosophy, from his dialogue the Parmenides, is a part of that investigation. In fact, Plato provides a refutation of the atomist philosophy in the Parmenides. A significant amount of scholarship has been accomplished that demonstrates the currents of Lucretian atomism in Machiavellis Florence. Evidence is supplied as to Machiavellis exposure to the Lucretian text, and the book then proceeds to investigate the transformational arguments of the Discourses On Livy itself. Machiavellis Discourses are saturated with terminology that is borrowed from physics: materia (Matter), corpo (body), forma (form), accidente (accident). English translators have usually employed some theory as to which tradition of physics Machiavelli is relying upon, in order to conduct their translations. By borrowing the terminology of Lucretian physics, Machiavelli becomes able to conceive of the people in a political society as something less than human: as matter or materia without form. In my analysis of Machiavellis deployment of the concepts from Lucretian physics, it is attempted to unveil the brutality that is inherent in Machiavellis new definitions of the elements of politics, and the general hostility of his political science to the Aristotelian concept of the human being as political animal. The classical physics of Aristotle, which Machiavelli has rejected for a model, indicates the forward looking momentum of natural beings. For Aristotle, nature intends human political society as the arena for human fulfillment. In Aristotelian physics, nature aims at an end in generation, i.e. at a culmination of the natural being in its proper condition of excellence. For human beings, this is justice, the quality of relationships that makes happiness possible. In Machiavelli, a new politicized physics is revealed. In Machiavellis model, the human beings of formed matter are repeatedly sent, through new institutions and methods of government, back to their beginnings, i.e. to a condition of isolation, destitution, injury, and pain. The last chapter of the book concludes with an examination of the particular institutions and methods that Machiavelli holds out to us for employment, if his new vision of a republic is to be realized.

Robert J. Roecklein: author's other books


Who wrote Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Acknowledgements

I would first like to thank Dr. Steve Hicks, the director of the School of Humanities and Social Sciences here at Penn State Erie, the Behrend College. Steve has been very supportive of my research, and I am much appreciative. Dr. Robert Speel, the chair of the Political Science Department, has been equally supportive. Dr. Zachary Irwin, with his charm and wisdom, has helped me to keep a balanced perspective about my efforts. I feel greatly indebted to these three individuals for these reasons and considerably more.

Dr. Juan Fernandez-Jimenez, chairman of the department of modern languages here at Behrend College, is a great friend and a valued colleague. We have spent a considerable number of hours together discussing politics, philosophy, and the current enterprise of education. He and his lovely wife Ms. Lupe Alvear-Madrid, bring warmth, friendship and a very stimulating culture to our school. I am very grateful for it.

My mentors and colleagues in the teaching of rhetoric at Behrend have provided me with great friendship, support, and wise counsel. Dr. John Champagne deserves special mention in this regard. Dr. Mary Connerty, associate program director, has benefited us all by her leadership. I would like to thank Dr. Teresa Caruso and Dr. Sharon Gallagher for sharing their ideas with me, and for being willing to entertain some of mine.

Dr. Stephen Eric Bronner, Professor II at Rutgers University, was the first professor for whom I worked as a graduate student. A relationship was then formed that has provided me with countless blessings over the years. A mentor and a friend, Steve has been there for me as I have worked on my books. His encouragement and perspective, his help in all manner of ways, could not be easily described. I am very grateful for my friendship with Steve, and for the time he has taken out of a packed schedule to work with me.

Jana Hodges-Kluck, associate editor for philosophy and the classics at Lexington Books, has now shepherded me through the completion of two books. Writers depend on their editors. For advice on the preparation of revisions, and for multiple kinds of commentary on my manuscript, Ms. Hodges-Kluck has done me inestimable services. I think there is certainly good fortune, though not of the Machiavellian kind, that has allowed this partnership to take place. I would also like to thank Mr. Eric Wrona, editorial assistant at Lexington books, for the swiftness and accuracy of his management of this books progress at several important stages.

I owe a debt of considerable thanks to the anonymous reviewer who read the manuscript for Lexington Books and who made insightful, relevant comments and criticisms. This is a better book for having undergone a vigorous peer review process. I am grateful for the care with which the reviewer analyzed my arguments and suggested improvements.

Mr. Joshua Testa, a former student of mine who is now in graduate studies for a doctorate in political science at Kent State University, is someone with whom I talk quite frequently. The focus of our discussion is usually political philosophy, and the ideas that we are both working on. Josh is a great sounding board, and a very promising political philosopher in the making.

I am grateful to all the students at Behrend College, with whom I have developed several of the arguments contained herein. Jacob Bowen, Brian Forfa, Jason Kinsel, and Joshua Snyder merit special acknowledgement. The passion and dedication of these students did much to fire my own.

Patrick Moloney, formerly of Victoria University in New Zealand, has been my closest friend in academia for over twenty years. Our friendship was formed in graduate school, because I did not know how to make a proper cup of tea. Pat has always encouraged my work, and he has also always reminded me of the importance of laughter. Political philosophy needs to remember laughter, especially when it is laboring on the darkly great work of Niccolo Machiavelli. Not that there is much of true humor in Machiavelli. Decently bred people would not be seen to laugh in those moments when the Florentine would like for us to do so.

My family makes me happy, something Aristotle would approve of. My sister Ann Marie Rice, whose great sense of humor makes the sun shine brighter, and my brother Neil C. Roecklein, with his quiet labor and determination, know of my feelings for them. My brother-in-law Kevin Rice Sr. is among my oldest friends. My nephews Christopher and Kevin Jr. are young men starting out in life. Their lives and endeavors bring joy to all of us.

I have dedicated this book to my best friend John Fragala. In the day-to-day life of a political philosopher, it becomes clear, that a man cannot bear the heavy burdens of argument all on his own. He must have friendship which shares the purpose, which divides the psychological strain, which keeps at least one foot planted in the world of today. John has borne a great deal of the weight of this project, effortlessly, generously, devotedly, and with a kindness that is rare and valuable. It can truly be said, that I could not have completed this book without his help.

Introduction
Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought

Whether or not Niccolo Machiavelli is an advocate for popular government has long been a pressing issue in political philosophy. Some scholars point to his famous work, The Prince, which suggests the Florentines devotion to a one-man rule politically compatible with an oppressed citizenry. Other and more numerous scholars point to Machiavellis Discourses on Livy, which seems to celebrate the people as the very guardian of freedom in a true republic. This level of discussion, however, might not be adequate.

There is another dimension to Machiavellis political science that bears upon the issue of popular participation, which involves the history of Epicurean philosophy. An analysis of Epicurean philosophy, and evidence for Machiavellis involvement with this tradition, constitute major objectives of this study. Epicurean philosophy does not bring before us, front and center, the issue of political participation. Rather, what it brings before us is the distinction between a few knowers and the many who do not know. In Epicurean philosophy, the great multitude of the people is regarded as oblivious to the truth of things, right down to the truth of particular facts. To the extent that Epicurean philosophy is indeed a part of Machiavellis political science, therefore, a simple exhortation to popular participation would hardly indicate the classically republican model. For if the people are regarded, insofar as they participate in politics, as unknowing ciphers whose actions must be coerced and prefigured by a philosophical rule, the functions of deliberation and choice would not under those circumstances fall within the circumference of their practices.

In the view of Quentin Skinner, to take one example, Machiavelli holds out the prospect of civic participation for all. In Skinners analysis, it is thus Machiavellis fundamental conviction that a life of political involvement must not only be made available to every citizen on equal terms, but must be made as alluring as possible to men of the highest talents.

Both of these ideals, of substantive deliberation and self-denying virtue, would fall afoul of a doctrine that is actually Epicurean in its foundations. In Epicurus analysis, obligation to anything other than the pains and pleasures of the self is the de facto definition of barbarity and stupidity. And, on behalf of the common run of human beings, since they are thought by Epicurean philosophy to fundamentally lack the knowledge which would make available to them truth of fact, their suitability for deliberation would be repudiated from the start. The question then greatly concerns the degree to which the foundations of Machiavellis political science are Epicurean; which in turn would concern the degree to which Lucretius, the Epicurean poet and one of Machiavellis favorite writers, actually exerted an influence on him.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought»

Look at similar books to Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought»

Discussion, reviews of the book Machiavelli and Epicureanism: An Investigation into the Origins of Early Modern Political Thought and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.