DISJUNCTIVISM
OXFORD BIBLIOGRAPHIES ONLINE RESEARCH GUIDE
Berit Brogaard
University of Missouri, St. Louis
2011 by Oxford University Press, Inc.
ISBN: 9780199808755
TABLE OF CONTENTS
OXFORD BIBLIOGRAPHIES ONLINE RESEARCH GUIDE
From
OXFORD BIBLIOGRAPHIES ONLINE | Philosophy
Authority and Innovation for Scholarly Research Written by a leading international authority and bearing the Oxford University Press stamp of excellence, this article is a definitive guide to the most important resources on the topic. The article combines annotated citations, expert recommendations, and narrative pathways through the most important scholarly sources in both print and online formats. All materials recommended in this article were reviewed by the author, and the article has been organized in tiers ranging from general to highly specialized, saving valuable time by allowing researchers to easily narrow or broaden their focus among only the most trusted scholarly sources. This is just one of many articles within the subject area of Atlantic History, which is itself just one of the many subjects covered by Oxford Bibliographies Onlinea revolutionary resource designed to cut through academic information overload by guiding researchers to exactly the right book chapter, journal article, website, archive, or data set they need.
WHY OBO?
For faculty and researchers:
- Jumpstarts the research process by directing you to the best print and online sources available
- Offers high-level overviews of scholarship to get you quickly up to speed on topics outside your area of expertise
- OpenURL and full-text DOIs offer seamless linking to your librarys catalog, OCLC WorldCat, and Google Books
- Provides a useful tool for preparing syllabi, writing and research assignments
For undergraduate and graduate students:
- Provides undergraduates with an indispensable introduction to the literature on major and minor topics within their field
- Promotes critical thinking about sources and gives students the means to negotiate and identify quality scholarship
- Helps graduate students prepare for qualifying exams, providing guidance on key works of scholarship
For Librarians:
- Designed in consultation with active researchers, Oxford Bibliographies Online offers an essential resource for managing academic information overload
- Expert recommendations on the best works availablefrom books and journal articles to archives, websites, and data setsmakes this the ultimate collection development tool
- Increases usage of the online journals and databases your institution subscribes to by seamlessly directing researchers to those sources
- Supports print discoverability by allowing patrons to link directly to the online catalog through OpenURL and full-text DOIs
* Functionality available through the oxfordbibligoraphiesonline.com platform only
To learn more, visit www.oxfordbibliographiesonline.com or send this form to your librarian to benefit from an institution-wide FREE trial.
INTRODUCTION
Disjunctivismwith respect to bodily or mental states or reasons of kind Sis the view that S-states (or reasons) can be divided into more fundamental kinds of entities that have different kinds of entities as their essential constituents, or that differ in what kind of information, evidence, or motivation they provide. The best-known version of disjunctivism is an offspring of one of the oldest theories of perception, known as naive realism. To a first approximation, naive realism is the view that perceptions have mind-independent objects among their constituents. Many historical philosophers (from John Locke to Bertrand Russell) argued that naive realism must be rejected on the grounds that hallucinations are perceptual experiences that do not have mind-independent objects among their constituents. Their reasoning, roughly, went as follows: Perceptions and hallucinations are constitutively on a par. Hence, either both perceptions and hallucinations have mind-independent objects among their constituents or neither does. As hallucinations do not have mind-independent objects among their constituents, neither do perceptions. Contemporary philosophers have resurrected the theory by treating perception and hallucination as having different kinds of entities among their constituents. This version of naive realism has come to be known as the disjunctive conception of experience. Epistemological disjunctivism and disjunctivism about phenomenal belief, or what I shall call introspective disjunctivism, have also gained popularity in recent years. Epistemological disjunctivism is the view that only genuine cases of perception provide (good) perceptual evidence. Introspective disjunctivism is the view that genuine phenomenal beliefs have phenomenal properties among their constituents. More recently, disjunctivist accounts of bodily movements, abilities, and reasons for action have entered the philosophical scene. These accounts treat the relevant bodily or mental entities as divisible into different kinds that have different kinds of entities among their constituents, or that satisfy different epistemic or practical constraints. This entry focuses on the contemporary debate about the different varieties of disjunctivism just outlined, including their characterization, their motivation, and their potential shortcomings.
GENERAL OVERVIEWS
There are several good introductory overviews of the debate about disjunctivism. One is Crane 2008, which offers a good overview of the arguments from illusion and hallucination. Traditionally, these arguments were taken to motivate sense-data theory. Disjunctivism is now one of the more common ways of responding to the arguments. Haddock and Macpherson 2008 provides an overview of the distinct forms of disjunctivism traditionally defended in the literature. They classify Snowdon as an experiential disjunctivist, McDowell as an epistemic disjunctivist, and Martin as a phenomenal disjunctivist (see Metaphysical Disjunctivism for more information). Another excellent overview article is Byrne and Logue 2008, which also provides an overview of the distinct kinds of disjunctivism. Byrne and Logue distinguish among Hintonesque disjunctivism, which denies that there is a common structural element in good and bad cases of perception; Austinian disjunctivism, which holds that there is a fundamental difference between the object one is aware of in good and bad cases of perception; and epistemological disjunctivism, which holds that there is a difference in the epistemic status of the perceptual evidence provided in good and bad cases of perception. They also discuss how different authors classify illusions. Finally, they offer an argument against disjunctivism that turns on the disjunctivist dictum that there is no specific mental state or event common to the good and the bad case. These authors also provide a good introductory overview in their collection Disjunctivism: Contemporary Readings (Byrne and Logue 2009). Here they distinguish the different kinds of disjunctivism and give a concise overview of the arguments for and against. Fish 2009 and Soteriou 2009 are good entries on disjunctivism. Campbell 2002 defends naive realism for the good case. Finally, the Chalmers and Bourget online entry on disjunctivism, part of the PhilPapers directory of articles and books on philosophy, is updated regularly.
Byrne, Alex, and Heather Logue. Either/Or. In Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge . Edited by Adrian Haddock and Fiona Macpherson, 5794. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
An accessible overview of different kinds of metaphysical and epistemological disjunctivism. Also contains a useful classification of metaphysical disjunctivism in terms of how illusions are treated, and two arguments against metaphysical disjunctivism.
Next page