Logic Overview ISyllogistic Terms (see )
Every standard-form categorical syllogism has exactly three terms, to wit:
The major term is the predicate term of the conclusion (P).
The minor term is the subject term of the conclusion (S).
The middle term is the term appearing in both premises but not in the conclusion (M).
The premise in which the major term appears is the major premise.
The premise in which the minor term appears is the minor premise.
A syllogism is in standard form when its three propositions are in exactly this order: major premise, minor premise, conclusion.
Every proposition in a categorical syllogism must be one of the following four:
An A propositionuniversal affirmative | (e.g., All politicians are liars.) |
An E propositionuniversal negative | (e.g., No politicians are liars.) |
An I propositionparticular affirmative | (e.g., Some politicians are liars.) |
An O propositionparticular negative | (e.g., Some politicians are not liars.) |
The mood of a syllogism is determined by the types of its three propositions, AAA, EIO, etc.
The figure of a standard-form syllogism is determined by the position of its middle term:
1st: Middle term is the subject of the major premise and the predicate of the minor premise.
2nd: Middle term is the predicate of both premises.
3rd: Middle term is the subject of both premises.
4th: Middle term is the predicate of the major premise and the subject of the minor premises.
Logic Overview IIValid Forms of the Categorical Syllogism (see )
Any syllogistic form is completely determined by the combination of its mood and figure. There are exactly 15 valid forms of the categorical syllogism, each with a unique name:
Rules governing every valid categorical syllogism:
The syllogism must contain exactly three terms, used consistently.
The middle term of the syllogism must be distributed in at least one premise.
If either term is distributed in the conclusion, it must be distributed in the premises.
A valid syllogism cannot have two negative premises.
If either premise of the syllogism is negative, the conclusion must be negative.
From two universal premises no particular conclusion may be drawn.
Logic Overview IIIThe Seven Stages of Scientific Investigation: The Scientific Method (see )
Identify the problem
Devise preliminary hypotheses
Collect additional facts
Formulate a refined explanatory hypothesis
Deduce consequences from the refined hypothesis
Test the consequences deduced
Apply the theory
Logic Overview IVMills Methods of Inductive Inference (see )
The Method of Agreement: The one factor or circumstance that is common to all the cases of the phenomenon under investigation is likely to be the cause (or effect) of that phenomenon.
A B C D occur together with w x y z.
A E F G occur together with w t u v.
Note
(Note: A term is distributed when the proposition in which the term appears refers to all members of the class to which the term refers. Thus, in the proposition All humans are mortal the term humans is distributed, but the term mortal is not.)
INTRODUCTION TO
LOGIC
INTRODUCTION TO
LOGIC
FOURTEENTH EDITION
Irving M. Copi
University of Hawaii
Carl Cohen
University of Michigan
Kenneth McMahon
Hawaii Pacific University
First published 2011, 2009, 2005, 2002, 1998 by Pearson Education, Inc.
Published 2016 by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
Copyright 2011, 2009, 2005, 2002, 1998 Taylor & Francis
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Notice:
Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
Credits and acknowledgments borrowed from other sources and reproduced, with permission, in this textbook appear on appropriate page within text (or on ).
Many of the designations by manufacturers and seller to distinguish their products are claimed as trademarks. Where those designations appear in this book, and the publisher was aware of a trademark claim, the designations have been printed in initial caps or all caps.
ISBN-13: 9780205820375 (hbk)
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Copi, Irving M.
Introduction to logic. 14th ed./Irving M. Copi, Carl Cohen, K. D.
McMahon.
p. cm.
Includes index.
1. LogicTextbooks. I. Cohen, Carl, 1931- II. McMahon, K. D. (Kenneth D.) III. Title.
BC108.C69 2011
160dc22
2010036272
We dedicate this fourteenth edition of Introduction to Logic to the many thousands of students and their teachers, at hundreds of universities in the United States and around the world, who have relied on earlier editions of the book, and have greatly helped to improve it, over five decades.
Brief Contents
Contents
In a republican nation, whose citizens are to be led by persuasion and not by force, the art of reasoning becomes of the first importance.
Thomas Jefferson
L ogic has sometimes been defined as the science of the laws of thought. This is inaccurate. Thinking is one of the processes studied by psychologists. If thought refers to any process that occurs in peoples minds, not all thought is an object of study for the logician. Thus, one may think of a number between one and ten without doing any reasoning about it. One may also remember, imagine, free-associate, or perform any of a number of mental processes. All reasoning is thinking, but not all thinking is reasoning. The laws that describe the movements of the mind are psychological laws rather than logical principles. To define logic in this way is to include too much.
Logic has also been called the science of reasoning. This is better, but reasoning is a kind of thinking in which inference takes place and conclusions are drawn from premises. This process is extremely complex, characterized by a combination of trial and error, occasionally illuminated by flashes of insight. Logicians are not concerned with the ways in which the mind arrives at its conclusions in the process of reasoning; they are concerned only with the correctness of the completed process: Does the conclusion reached