Logic of The Future
Edited by
Charles S. Peirce
Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen
Volume 2/2
Peirceana
Volume 2/2
ISBN 9783110740356
e-ISBN (PDF) 9783110740462
e-ISBN (EPUB) 9783110740530
Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek
The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de.
2021 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
Charles S. Peirce
Logic of the Future, Volume 2/2
Peirceana
Edited by
Francesco Bellucci and Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen
Volume 2
Charles S. Peirce
Logic of the Future
Writings on Existential Graphs
Part 2: The 1903 Lowell Lectures
Edited by
Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen
DE GRUYTER
ISBN 978-3-11-074035-6
e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-074046-2
e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-3-11-074053-0
ISSN 2698-7155
Library of Congress Control Number: 2021932713
Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek
The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de.
2021 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
Typesetting: Jukka Nikulainen
www.degruyter.com
Acknowledgments
The work on the Logic of the Future has taken over fifteen years to complete. A considerable number of people and sources of support have accumulated over the years that are to be acknowledged and deeply thanked for their respective contributions.
An edition on Peirces graphical logic was conceived during the class I gave at the University of Helsinki on Peirces Logic and Philosophy in autumn 2004. At that time, it became obvious to me that Peirces logic can never be adequately studied, let alone deeply researched, understood and put into a perspective within the history of ideas, without comprehensive editions.
It was the students of that class of 2004 that ignited the work on the present volumes. Its 20-odd students, including Jukka Nikulainen, Henrik Rydenfelt, Lauri Snellman, Lauri Jrvilehto, Michael von Boguslawski, Harry Alanen, Peter Schulman and many others whose names I have forgotten, provided initial assistance in manuscript inspection and transcription.
There is one person without whom this edition would not have been possible to be produced at all. My long-term research assistant, Jukka Nikulainen, who has served as a technical editor of these volumes and has provided the first-ever LATEX package (EGpeirce) by which one can now typeset any graph, special mark or symbol that ever emanated from Peirces hand, with ease and uniformity. Jukka also encoded a large majority of the hundreds of complex graphs that appear in the volumes, improving the package along the way and adding new features to it. We believe that by now everything that Peirce ever designed and wanted to design as a special graph, type, character, mark or signa plethora of his typographical eccentricities notwithstandinghave been incorporated into the functionality of the Peirce LATEX package. And much more is available in it than is in fact needed for the purposes of compiling the present editions. Peirces ethics of notation dictates that pieces of notation are just as important as the prose overall, and that whenever new notation is introduced, reasons for it are not to be taken lightly. Design and typesetting practices have to follow suit, and indeed Jukka has considerably assisted the production of the CRCs of these volumes for the press, honing the notations and checking many of the transcriptions as I slowly progressed with them. He has also searched and compiled information on many of Peirces references as well as prepared both the index of names and the index of words. Nikulainen, above all, deserves to be acknowledged as having done an amount of work vastly exceeding anything that is to be expected of a technical editor probably years rather than months since 2004in order to bring the edition into its present shape.
Claudia Cristalli also went out of her way in helping to bring the edition into its near- completion.Without hermany suggestions and concrete advice on organisation and presentation of the material, the progress on these volumes might have slouched altogether. In particular, she gave valuable proposals on organising the editorial, introductory and survey parts.
Francesco Bellucci deserves an equally immeasurable gratitude for pressing on with finalising these volumes. Not only did he check many of the items and transcriptions but also closely researched their content, coming up with important perspectives concerning their interpretation. The volumes and their editorial introductions have benefitted enormously from our scholarly collaboration over the last several years.
Marc Champagne and Liu Xinwen have followed the progress of this project over the years. Both have provided a number of comments and corrections on the introductory parts, and deserve a special thanks for such laborious deeds.
These editions would probably have not seen the light of day had it not been for the enthusiasm and intellectual support of Nathan Houser, with whom I regularly conversed on the prospects of such a work ever since my stay at the Peirce Edition Project in the autumn of 2005 as a post-doctoral Fulbright grantee. It is thanks to Nathans vocal accentuation on the importance of bringing about a thematic edition on graphs, and above all the unprecedented scholarship that he represents in the Peirce community, that have kept me going with the work. Andr De Tienne, Director of the Peirce Edition Project, has been equally supportive of the enterprise from the get-go. Conversations with him have supplied vital links and clues by which one could go about navigating the amazing mazes that the literary output of this American mind puts before us.
Over the years, John Sowa, Matthew Moore and Helmut Pape have all provided experienced advice, John on the topical relevance of Peirces graphical logic, and Matt and Helmut on the challenges of editing Peirces papers for a thematic collection. Susan Haack has followed the project with interest, and I do not doubt that any new material that might be found in these texts would only support the conclusions she has already arrived at.
My first graduate class on Peirce was given by Risto Hilpinen, who taught logic and philosophy of science at the University of Turku in early 1990s and who was the first to notice that Peirce had arrived at semantic and logical ideas surprisingly similar to those reached much later by others, in particular the game-theoretical semantics independently discovered by Jaakko Hintikka in the 1960s. I am honoured to have an opportunity of including an Introductory Note from Prof. Hilpinen.
Discussionswith the late Jaakko Hintikka in 20002015 on Peirces logic have enabled me to put many of the related contributions into a sharper perspective. ), but can be explained by the similarities in the methods of logic and the significance placed on having good logical notations, the relational apparatus of thought, the value placed on proofs, and the semantic (or model-theoretic, semeiotic, notational) outlook on ones philosophical investigations. Both Peirce and Hintikka had put scientific and human inquiry ahead of bare epistemology: both advocated an action-first epistemology. That there is reality and truth in such philosophy is reflected in the comment I once received from Jaakko on my presentation that explored connections between the two thinkers. I had suggested that the sheer number of them makes one almost believe in reincarnation, to which he replied: Yes, but who incarnated whom?