• Complain

Leszek Kolakowski - Metaphysical Horror

Here you can read online Leszek Kolakowski - Metaphysical Horror full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 1988, publisher: Blackwell Pub, genre: Religion. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Leszek Kolakowski Metaphysical Horror
  • Book:
    Metaphysical Horror
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Blackwell Pub
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    1988
  • Rating:
    4 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 80
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Metaphysical Horror: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Metaphysical Horror" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

This is about nothing less than the search for the Absolute. The author argues that this search has a persistent cultural foundation. He attempts to show that in its most radical forms - the Neoplatonic One and the Cartesian cogito - the Absolute slides into nothing. There seems to be both a logical and historical inevitability in the process. Kolakowski is not content, however, with this tendency of the Absolute to disintegrate. He believes that this apparently discouraging result does not deprive the inquiry of its legitimacy. He offers no solutions to the intractable question, but rather a tentative, playful way out.

Leszek Kolakowski: author's other books


Who wrote Metaphysical Horror? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Metaphysical Horror — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Metaphysical Horror" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Metaphysical

Horror

Leszek Kolakowski

Basil Blackwell

First published 1988

Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford 0X4 1JF, UK

Basil Blackwell Inc.

432 Park Avenue South, Suite 1503 New York, NY 10016, USA

All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for thepurposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, inany form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording orotherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher .

Except in the United States of America, this book issold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise,be lent, re-sold, hired out, or otherwise circulated without the publishersprior consent in any form of binding or cover other than that in which it ispublished and without a similar condition including this condition beingimposed on the subsequent purchaser.

BritishLibrary Cataloguing in Publication Data

Kolakowski, Leszek Metaphysical horror,

. 1. Metaphysics

1. Title

110 B945.K7/

ISBN 0-631-15959-2

Libraryof Congress Cataloging in Publication Data

Kolakowski, Leszek.

Metaphysical horror / Leszek Kolakowski. p . cm.

Includes index.

ISBN 0-631-15959-2 . Metaphysics. 2.Philosophy. I. Title. B4691.K5863M47 1988 190dcl9

Typeset in 12 on 14pt Garamond by DMB (Typesetting), Abingdon, Oxon .

Printed in Great Britain by Billing and Sons Ltd, Worcester

Contents

OnPhilosophers 1 On Philosophy 1 On Philosophys Self-martyrdom 2 ItsSelf-derision 7 Its Self-yearning. Jaspers (1) Its Survival 11 On What Is Real 11 Cartesian Dreams.

Recyclingthe Cogito (1) 21 Alibi. The Curse of Time 27 The Absolute (1) 29 The Absolute (2) 33 Divine Persons and Unpersons.

Is GodGood? Cruor Dei 36 Damascius and Two Kinds of Nothingness 43 DivineNothingness in Christianity 49 On All PossibleLanguages (1) 51 Recycling the Cogito (2) 56 On Husserl 59 OnMerleau-Ponty 61

Ego as aQuasi-absolute 66 On De-Cartesianization 69 On Spinoza 7 3 On Jaspers (2) 7 5 Leibniz and All Possible Worlds 77 On Creation, Divine and Human 82Alter-ego 96 On All Possible Languages (2) 98 Reading the World -113

Index ofNames -121

Metaphysical Horror

ON PHILOSOPHERS

A modernphilosopher who has never experienced the feeling of being a charlatan is sucha shallow mind that his work is probably not worth reading.

For centuries philosophy asserted its legitimacy by asking andanswering questions it had inherited from the Socratic and pre-Socratic legacy,that is, how to distinguish the real from the unreal, the true from the false,the good from the evil. There is one man with whom all European philosophersidentify themselves, even if they dismiss his ideas altogether. This isSocrates - a philosopher who is unable to identify himself with this archetypalfigure does not belong to this civilization.

ON PHILOSOPHY

At acertain moment, however, philosophers had to face, and to cope with, a simple,painfully undeniable fact: among questions that have sustained the life ofEuropean philosophy for two and a half millennia not asingle one has ever been solved to our general satisfaction; all of them remaineither controversial or invalidated by philosophers decree. Tobe a nominalist or anti-nominalist is culturally and intellectually as possibletoday as it was in the twelfth century; to believe or not to believe that onemay tell phenomena from the essence is as admissible as it used to be inancient Greece; and so is to think that the distinction between good and evilis a contingent convention or that it is embedded in the order of things. You may still be a respectable person whether you believe or refuse to believein God; no standards in our civilization prevent you from thinking thatlanguage reflects reality or that it creates it; and you arenot barred from good society if you accept or dismiss the semanticconcept of truth. Whatever matters in philosophy - and this means: whatever makesphilosophy matter at all in life - is subject to the same options that havepersisted since the unidentifiable moment when independent thought,disregarding the mythological legacy as a source of authority, arose in ourcivilization. The vocabulary and the forms of expression have changed, to besure, and many mutations have occurred - thanks to the number of great mindswho appear occasionally in every century - yet the kernel which keepsphilosophy alive is unchanged.

ON PHILOSOPHYS SELF-MARTYRDOM

Variousstrategies have been devised to deal with thisapparently self-defeating status of philosophy. The least reliable but the mostsuccessful, at least in terms of a philosophers self-confidence, consists indenying that the situation just described obtains at all. Some questions aredeclared meaningless and thus non-questions; the meaningful ones are soluble,not unlike scientific problems, and many have actually been solved - if somepeople are not ready to accept the solution, they only thereby display theirintellectual ineptitude. Die-hard analytical philosophers and old-stylephenomenologists who openly philosophize within the framework of this strategyare now, however numerous, endangered species.

Thesecond strategy embraces a variety of relativistic ways out. The meaning ofphilosophical questions, like all others, is defined either by the rules of alinguistic game or by a historical setting, a specific civilization withinwhich they were uttered, or else by the considerations of usefulness. There areno obligatory standards of rationality and therefore there is no such thing asvalidity tout court. A philosophical truth, a solution of the problemmay indeed be valid but, if so, it invalid in relation to a game, a culture ora collective or individual goal. We simply cannot go any further, we have no tools to force the door leading us beyond language, beyond a set ofcontingent cultural norms or beyond practical imperatives which mould ourthinking process.

Thereare two basic interpretations of this relativistic approach:latitudinarian-anarchist and restrictive. In the former, anything goes that isadmissible or good (linguistically, culturally, practically); the differencebetween, say, believing and not believing in the Devil is similar to thedifference between a vegetarian and a meat-eater or between monogamous andpolygamous social orders. Some cultures, or some games, may forbid or imposebelief in the Devil, some prescribe dietary norms, some do not. If the language of the culture I am an inhabitant of allows for bothvegetarian and non-vegetarian diets, I am right in either choice on theassumption that it serves me well, and the same applies to belief or disbeliefin the Devil. If a society imposes monogamy on its members, and survives,monogamy is right and thus true: at any rate scientific, philosophical and religious beliefs enjoy no other kind of truth.Rules come first, reality hinges on them. God does not exist in Albania, but hevery much does in Persia; Heisenbergs principle is valid now but was not inancient Athens.

Thetrouble with this generous interpretation of relativism is that although itmight satisfy some philosophers, it appears poorly designed when confrontedwith the inveterate (albeit regrettable, in their view) mental customs of mankind, including scientists. Conforming with thesecustoms, when I say the Devil tempted me, I mean that the Devil tempted me. A linguistic, historical or utilitarian relativism allows for a setof rules within which it is permissible to say the Devil tempted me, but whensaying so I am supposed to mean precisely that: it is permissible according tothe rules I live by to say the Devil tempted me (or to say the sum ofthree angles of any triangle is equal to two right angles). In otherwords, I have to obey a rule ordering me to keep in mind that whatever I amsaying I am not saying that something is the case but that - nothing being thecase - the rules give me the right to say so: this amounts to stating that we all ought to speak only in a kind of metalanguage. Thusphrased, this prescription might sound wierd, but I do not see How a generous relativism could avoid it without beingsuspected of falling into the rationalist prejudices of old, Assuming, for thesake of argument, that the prescription can be both uttered and appliedconsistently, it is obviously at odds with the dominant rules of speaking. Thequestion is: why should the prevailing rules be abrogated in favour of the relativistic ones? If the rule about therelativity of rules is not supposed to be relative itself, it is bound to be anarbitrary decree, and if it is as relative as the rules to which it applies, ithas no more force than the opposite one and the statement nothing is the caseis in no better positionthanitis not true that nothing is the case. And it should be observed that both statements nothing isthe case and it is not true that nothing is the case are not uttered in ametalanguage.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Metaphysical Horror»

Look at similar books to Metaphysical Horror. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Metaphysical Horror»

Discussion, reviews of the book Metaphysical Horror and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.