• Complain

Graham Hubbs - Pragmatism, Law, and Language

Here you can read online Graham Hubbs - Pragmatism, Law, and Language full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2013, publisher: Routledge, genre: Romance novel. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Graham Hubbs Pragmatism, Law, and Language

Pragmatism, Law, and Language: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Pragmatism, Law, and Language" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

This volume puts leading pragmatists in the philosophy of language, including Robert Brandom, in contact with scholars concerned with what pragmatism has come to mean for the law. Each contribution uses the resources of pragmatism to tackle fundamental problems in the philosophy of language, the philosophy of law, and social and political philosophy. In many chapters, the version of pragmatism deployed proves a fruitful approach to its subject matter; in others, shortcomings of the specific brand of pragmatism are revealed. The result is a clearer understanding of what pragmatism has meant and can mean across these tightly related philosophical areas. The book, then, is itself pragmatism in action: it seeks to clarify its unifying concept by examining the practices that centrally involve it.

Graham Hubbs: author's other books


Who wrote Pragmatism, Law, and Language? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Pragmatism, Law, and Language — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Pragmatism, Law, and Language" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
1
A Hegelian Model of Legal Concept Determination

Robert B. Brandom

I. Indeterminateness and Rational Authority

The specter of skepticism haunts the philosophy of law. (Or at least, there is a neighborhood of that bustling city demarcated by a dominating concern with that potentially destructive apparition.) The engagement of early modern philosophy with skepticism traced out an arc, from the epistemological skepticism from which Descartes recoiled to the more radical semantic skepticism that Kant was concerned to forestall. Where Descartess inquiry into the conditions of the possibility of empirical knowledge could take for granted the subjects grasp of ideas that at least purported to represent how the objective world actually is, Kant dug deeper to investigate what is required to make intelligible the contentfulness of concepts in any sense that includes their objective representational purport. The sort of skepticism in the philosophy of law that I am concerned with here is also a specifically semantic skepticism. While there are legitimate epistemological questions about the practices and procedures by which various participants seek to know what the law is, the issues I am addressing are a matter rather of the intelligibility of the determinate contentfulness of the concepts that articulate laws. It is a mark of the distinctiveness of the realm of law that any semantic skeptical threat to the intelligibility of legal concepts as determinately contentful carries with it a collateral threat to the ontological status of legal statuses such as obligations and rights, which are instituted by laws.

The reason the rather abstract issue of semantic skepticism about the determinateness of legal concepts matters is that the rational authority of legal judgments and legal argumentation derives from the capacity of laws articulated by those concepts to serve as reasons justifying those judgments. The significance of the semantics of legal concepts lies in the normative pragmatic difference it makes. The content of concepts affects what one is committed and entitled to by applying those concepts in judgment and argumentation. Some kinds of semantic indeterminateness of legal concepts would undercut the rational credentials of legal arguments and the normative authority of legal

So one way of approaching the question of what sort of semantic skepticism must be avoided so as not to fall into legal nihilism about the rationality of legal argumentation and judgment concerning the application of legal concepts is to ask: what sort of determinateness of content is required for legal concepts to support assessments of what applications are and what are not rationally justified by principles expressed by the use of those concepts? One natural answer appeals to sharpness of the boundaries distinguishing what falls under the concepts and what does not. Here the operative ideal might be that cases specified in non-legal vocabulary (or in legal vocabulary that is in some sense at a different level from that being applied) should unambiguously determine the correct applicability of various legal concepts. Sharpness of boundaries is indeed a relevant issue, but I think we can see that if it is the rational justifiability of legal judgments and (so) the rational authority of legal norms (including those explicit in the form of laws or principles) that is potentially threatened by semantic indeterminateness, then we should look upstream of the issue of the definiteness of extension of legal concepts. What matters in the first instance is rather the definiteness of inference : of what considerations are reasons for and against judgments employing legal concepts.

Legal reasoninglike most medical or financial reasoning, and indeed, like almost all reasoning outside of mathematics and fundamental physicsis seldom formally, logically valid reasoning. The goodness of the inferences it relies on is rather material goodness. That is, the goodness of the reasoning essentially depends on the contents of the non-logical concepts it involves. Such reasoning can nonetheless be dispositive (and in that way like logical deduction). The inference from A is to the East of B, so B is to the West of A is a material inference, since it essentially depends on the contents of the non-logical concepts East and West . But it is dispositive nonetheless. But most legal reasoninglike most medical or financial reasoningis probative rather than dispositive. This need not mean that it has the right shape to be properly understood in terms of the weights of various evidential considerations. Rather it means that almost all the reasons considered are defeasible . The fact that p might provide very good reason for the conclusion that q. It need not follow that if in addition r is true, then p&r provides a good reason to conclude that q . In the medical case, the patients high fever is, by itself, a good reason to suspect bacterial infection. Add the information that the patient was just administered the anesthetic halothane and the conclusion no longer follows. However if in addition the patient has a high white blood-cell count, the presence of infection again becomes likelyunless the patient is leukemic. And so on. This defeasibility means that material inferences, including the inferences that articulate legal concepts, unlike logical ones, are in general non-monotonic : a good inference can be turned into a bad one by adding further premises.

It is just here that semantic indeterminateness threatens the rational authority of legal reasoning and (so) judgment. The sort of indeterminateness of legal concepts that would pose such a threat is indeterminateness concerning which inferences to legal conclusions (conclusions making essential use of legal concepts) are materially good or bad ones, and which additional considerations would either defeat them or reinstate those inferences. (Although talk of sharpness of boundaries of legal concepts can capture some of this concern, the home of such extensional talk is monotonic, indefeasible reasoning, and it is not particularly helpful in the non-monotonic realm of non-formal reasoning.) Insofar as it is not settled by the contents of legal concepts what would count as reasons for and against judgments articulated by the use of those concepts, and what additional premises would infirm or support those inferences, that indeterminateness will rob legal judgments in the vicinity of the sort of normative authority that can only derive from applications of legal concepts being subject to appropriately constrained assessments of the goodness of reasons for or against them. The semantic indeterminateness that would matter most, then, would be that concerning the complex network of non-monotonic inferential and incompatibility relations that articulates the contents of legal concepts.

Why might one think that legal concepts and principles are semantically indeterminate in this sense? One line of thought that has been influential over the last half century or so is Wittgensteins argument that, as I would put the point, norms explicit in the form of statable rules and principles are intelligible as underwriting determinate assessments of the correctness or incorrectness of various applications and inferences only against a background of implicit practical norms. Rules are not self-applying, and they do not explicitly say what follows from them or is incompatible with them. Consequences can be extracted from them only in the context of practices of distinguishing correct from incorrect inferences from those principles serving as premises. For any particular such inferential connection, or course, there might be another explicit rule that told us it was correct to draw that conclusion from the original principle. But the lesson of Lewis Carrolls fable Achilles and the Tortoise is that it does not make sense to think of all the inferences as codified in explicit principles. The regress of explicit interpretations must bottom out in something that is not an interpretation (in Wittgensteins sense of substituting one formulation of a rule for another). One cannot dispense with constellations of practices that implicitly treat some applications of concepts as correct and others as incorrect. Norms explicit in the form of rules or principles necessarily float on a supporting sea of norms implicit in practice. Call this the regress of interpretations point.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Pragmatism, Law, and Language»

Look at similar books to Pragmatism, Law, and Language. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Pragmatism, Law, and Language»

Discussion, reviews of the book Pragmatism, Law, and Language and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.