• Complain

Bredo Johnsen - Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution

Here you can read online Bredo Johnsen - Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. year: 2017, publisher: Oxford University Press, genre: Science. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Bredo Johnsen Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution
  • Book:
    Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Oxford University Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2017
  • Rating:
    3 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 60
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

David Hume launched a historic revolution in epistemology when he showed that our theories about the world have no probability relative to what we think of as our evidence for them, hence that the distinction between justified and unjustified theories does not lie in their different probabilities relative to that evidence. However, allies in his revolution appeared only in the 20th century, in the persons of Sir Karl Popper, Nelson Goodman and W. V. Quine. Humes second great contribution to the field, which remains unrecognized to this day, was to propose what is now known as reflective equilibrium theory as the framework within which justified and unjustified theories are rightly distinguished. The core of this book comprises an account of these developments from Hume to Quine, an extension of reflective equilibrium theory that renders it a general theory of epistemic justification concerning our beliefs about the world, and an argument that all four of these thinkers would
have endorsed that extension. In chapters on Sextus, Descartes, Wittgensteins On Certainty, and other aspects of Humes epistemology I defend new readings of those philosophers writings on skepticism and note significant relationships among their views on matters bearing on the Humean revolution. Finally, in chapters on Hilary Putnams Brains in a Vat and Fred Dretskes contextualism - the only promising version of that view - I show that both fail to rule out the possible truth of radical skeptical hypotheses. This is not surprising, since those hypotheses are in fact possible. They are not, however, of any epistemological significance, since the justification of our beliefs about the world is a function of the extent to which bodies of beliefs to which they belong are in reflective equilibrium, and no extant conception of knowledge is of any epistemological interest.

Bredo Johnsen: author's other books


Who wrote Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Righting Epistemology Humes Revolution - image 1
Righting Epistemology

Righting Epistemology Humes Revolution - image 2

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the Universitys objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and certain other countries.

Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press

198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.

Oxford University Press 2017

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above.

You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.

CIP data is on file at the Library of Congress

ISBN 9780190662776

eISBN 9780190662790

In memory of

Anita

Contents

THE HEART of this book is an account of a historic epistemological revolution with an astonishing and depressing history. David Hume showed early in the eighteenth century that no theory about the nature of the physical world has any probability relative to our observational and memorial knowledge of bits of it, and this meant that we needed an entirely new way of understanding epistemic justification; the difference between justified and unjustified theories about the world could no longer be thought of as a matter of their differing probabilities relative to our evidence.

Nor did he stop there. So far is Hume from being the great skeptic of philosophical lore he proffered what would come to be known two centuries later as the reflective equilibrium theory of epistemic justification.

Regrettably, no one noticed, but in the twentieth century three distinguished philosophersSir Karl Popper, Nelson Goodman, and W. V. Quinebecame persuaded of the soundness of Humes underlying argument and set about rethinking epistemic justification.

After considering the work of Hume, Popper, Goodman, and Quine, I propose an extension of reflective equilibrium theory that is implicit in Quines epistemology. I argue that the extended theory is a completely general theory of epistemic justification for beliefs about the existence and nature of any physical world there may be, and that Quines three predecessors would quite certainly have endorsed it.

Other chapters address Sextus Empiricuss Outlines of Pyrrhonism I argue, inter alia, that Sextus is no skeptic, but rather a radical fallibilist concerning our beliefs about the world; that Descartess Meditation I has been badly misread as underwriting something called Cartesian skepticism; that the Humean argument should be recognized as the argument for radical skepticism within the classical tradition that he rejected; and that Wittgensteins protracted struggles in On Certainty can be seen to be leading him in the direction of a view much like Quines. More generally, these chapters do something by way of noting important relationships among these philosophers, and providing some historical and systematic context for Humes revolution.

In the appendices I argue that two significant recent attacks on skepticism fail: Hilary Putnams arguments that we cannot be brains in a vat, or even in a situation fully analogous to theirs, and Fred Dretskes version of contextualism. Putnams arguments simply fail on their own terms, and Dretskes view, though a promising version of contextualism, poses no threat to skepticism. I discuss them primarily to identify their failings, but also to underscore the fact that the possible truth of radical skeptical hypotheses has no epistemologically significant consequences; our beliefs are justified if they belong to certain kinds of bodies of beliefs that are in reflective equilibrium, and knowledge is simply of no epistemological interest on any extant conception of it.

I have benefited greatly from relationships with many teachers, colleagues, and students, beginning with the Wayne State University and Harvard University faculties of the 1960s. For most of my career, Roger Wertheimer has been the closest reader, sharpest critic, and most generous supporter of my work, and M. G. (Bob) Yoes, Jr., whose understanding of Goodman and Quine ran deep, was an inspiring colleague from the outset. Others for whose criticism, enlightenment, and encouragement I am grateful include Yuval Avnur, Jonathan Bennett, Lars Bergstrm, Joshua Brown, Richard Cartwright, Hector-Neri Castaeda, Ted Cohen, John Cooper, Russell Dancy, Fred Dretske, Catherine Elgin, Alireza Fatollahi, Carl Feierabend, Roderick Firth, Edmund Gettier, James Garson, Eric Gilbertson, Dane Gogoshin, Nelson Goodman, Gilbert Harman, Colin Howson, Alistair Isaac, Keith Lehrer, Benson Mates, John McNees, Robert Nozick, David Pears, John Perry, David Phillips, Alvin Plantinga, Lawrence Powers, W. V. Quine, David Sanford, Robert Sleigh, Gail Caldwell Stine, Tamara Tabo, Bas van Fraassen, Mary Viers, and Joshua Weisber.


Thomas Reids comment on Humes argument and purportedly consequent skepticism captures a common view of them:

A traveller of good judgment may mistake his way, and be unawares led into a wrong track; but, when it ends in a coal-pit, it requires no great judgment to know that he hath gone wrong, nor perhaps to find out what misled him.

See his Inquiry and Essays, edited by Keith Lehrer and R. E. Beanblossom (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975), 11 .

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (London, 17391740) .

David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (London, 1748) .

Colin Howson, Humes Problem (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000) .

Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by Benson Mates, in his The Skeptic Way (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996) .

The Philosophical Works of Descartes, translated by Elizabeth S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967) .

(hereafter PH) constitute one of the most striking passages in the history of philosophy:

When people search for something, the likely outcome is that either they find it or, not finding it, they accept that it cannot be found, or they continue to search. So also in the case of what is sought in philosophy, I think, some people have claimed to have found the truth, others have asserted that it cannot be apprehended, and others are still searching. Those who think that they have found it are the Dogmatists, properly so calledfor example, the followers of Aristotle and Epicurus, the Stoics, and certain others. The followers of Cleitomachus and Carneades, as well as other Academics, have asserted that it cannot be apprehended. The Skeptics continue to search. Hence it is with reason that the main types of philosophy are thought to be three in number: the Dogmatic, the Academic, and the Skeptic.reporting, like a chronicler, what now appears to us to be the case. (I, 14)

The Skeptic Way is a disposition to oppose phenomena [things that appear] and noumena [things that are thought] to one another in any way whatever, with the result that we are brought first to

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution»

Look at similar books to Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution»

Discussion, reviews of the book Righting Epistemology: Humes Revolution and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.