• Complain

Stephen Jay Gould - The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

Here you can read online Stephen Jay Gould - The Structure of Evolutionary Theory full text of the book (entire story) in english for free. Download pdf and epub, get meaning, cover and reviews about this ebook. City: Cambridge, Mass., year: 2002, publisher: Belknap Press, genre: Science. Description of the work, (preface) as well as reviews are available. Best literature library LitArk.com created for fans of good reading and offers a wide selection of genres:

Romance novel Science fiction Adventure Detective Science History Home and family Prose Art Politics Computer Non-fiction Religion Business Children Humor

Choose a favorite category and find really read worthwhile books. Enjoy immersion in the world of imagination, feel the emotions of the characters or learn something new for yourself, make an fascinating discovery.

Stephen Jay Gould The Structure of Evolutionary Theory
  • Book:
    The Structure of Evolutionary Theory
  • Author:
  • Publisher:
    Belknap Press
  • Genre:
  • Year:
    2002
  • City:
    Cambridge, Mass.
  • Rating:
    5 / 5
  • Favourites:
    Add to favourites
  • Your mark:
    • 100
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5

The Structure of Evolutionary Theory: summary, description and annotation

We offer to read an annotation, description, summary or preface (depends on what the author of the book "The Structure of Evolutionary Theory" wrote himself). If you haven't found the necessary information about the book — write in the comments, we will try to find it.

The worlds most revered and eloquent interpreter of evolutionary ideas offers here a work of explanatory force unprecedented in our time--a landmark publication, both for its historical sweep and for its scientific vision. With characteristic attention to detail, Stephen Jay Gould first describes the content and discusses the history and origins of the three core commitments of classical Darwinism: that natural selection works on organisms, not genes or species; that it is almost exclusively the mechanism of adaptive evolutionary change; and that these changes are incremental, not drastic. Next, he examines the three critiques that currently challenge this classic Darwinian edifice: that selection operates on multiple levels, from the gene to the group; that evolution proceeds by a variety of mechanisms, not just natural selection; and that causes operating at broader scales, including catastrophes, have figured prominently in the course of evolution. Then, in a stunning tour de force that will likely stimulate discussion and debate for decades, Gould proposes his own system for integrating these classical commitments and contemporary critiques into a new structure of evolutionary thought. In 2001 the Library of Congress named Stephen Jay Gould one of Americas eighty-three Living Legends--people who embody the quintessentially American ideal of individual creativity, conviction, dedication, and exuberance. Each of these qualities finds full expression in this peerless work, the likes of which the scientific world has not seen--and may not see again--for well over a century. Stephen Jay Gould is the Alexander Agassiz Professor of Zoology at Harvard University and Vincent Astor Visiting Professor of Biology at New York University. A MacArthur Prize Fellow, he has received innumerable honors and awards and has written many books, including Ontogeny and Phylogeny and Times Arrow, Times Cycle (both from Harvard).

Stephen Jay Gould: author's other books


Who wrote The Structure of Evolutionary Theory? Find out the surname, the name of the author of the book and a list of all author's works by series.

The Structure of Evolutionary Theory — read online for free the complete book (whole text) full work

Below is the text of the book, divided by pages. System saving the place of the last page read, allows you to conveniently read the book "The Structure of Evolutionary Theory" online for free, without having to search again every time where you left off. Put a bookmark, and you can go to the page where you finished reading at any time.

Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make
Footnotes

* Two of these three ranked as folk wisdom in Darwin's day and needed no further justification variation and inheritance (the mechanism of inheritance remained unknown, but its factuality could scarcely be doubted). Only the principle that all organisms produce more offspring than can possibly survive superfecundity, in Darwin's lovely term ran counter to popular assumptions about nature's benevolence, and required Darwin's specific defense in the Origin.

* As so much unnecessary rancor has been generated by simple verbal confusion among different meanings of this word, and not by meaningful conceptual disagreements, I should be clear that I intend only the purely descriptive definition when I write macroevolution that is, a designation of evolutionary phenomenology from the origin of species on up, in contrast with evolutionary change within populations of a single species. In so doing, I follow Goldschmidt's own definitional preferences (1940) in the book that established his apostasy within the Modern Synthesis. Misunderstanding has arisen because, to some, the world macroevolution has implied a theoretical claim for distinct causes, particularly for nonstandard genetic mechanisms, that conflict with, or do not occur at, the microevolutionary level. But Goldschmidt and I follow him here urged a nonconfrontational definition that could stand as a neutral descriptor for a set of results that would then permit evolutionists to pose the tough question without prejudice: does macroevolutionary phenomenology demand unique macroevolutionary mechanics? Thus, in this book, macroevolution is descriptive higher-level phenomenology, not pugnacious anti-Darwinian interpretation.

* I base this chapter on an exploration of the logic of argument in the first edition of the Origin of Species (1859). Provine (in lectures and personal communications) has argued that Darwinian historiography should focus on the definitive 6th edition of 1872, not only as Darwin's most considered and nuanced account, but primarily because this last edition has enjoyed such overwhelmingly greater influence through endless reprinting (continuing today) and translation into all major languages. The first edition had a print run of 1500 copies and sold out on the first day. I doubt that this original version ever reappeared in print before the facsimile edition edited by Mayr (1964), and this initial version remains rare relative to the ubiquitous sixth of almost every modern reprint. I agree with Provine's argument and, in fact, personally prefer the sixth edition for its subtleties on issues of macroevolution and adaptation. But I choose the first edition for this chapter as a necessary consequence of my idiosyncratic habits of historiographical work. I appreciate, and shamelessly exploit, the historian's central concern for social context and the multifarious sources of intellectual arguments. But I am an internalist at heart, though wearing the sheep's clothing of my own Darwinian heritage with its emphasis on external adaptation, part by part. I love to follow the logic of argument, to treat a great text as Cuvier considered an organism as an integrity, held together by sinews of logic (whatever the social or psychological origin of any particular item). I love to explore these connections, and to grasp the beauty of the totality. Thus, I prefer to practice the rather old-fashioned technique of explication des textes (see my longer rationale and attempt in Gould, 1987b, on Burnet, Hutton and Lyell). For this exercise, the first edition, despite its hurried composition as the scourge of Ternate breathed down Darwin's neck, represents the most coherent document, before all subsequent, externally-driven adaptations to critical commentary fixed the flaws and hedged the difficulties. Errors and inconsistencies build vital parts of integrity; I may share Cuvier's concern with necessary connections, but not his belief in optimal design. True integrity, in a messy world, implies rough edges, which not only have a beauty of their own, but also provide our best evidence for the logic of argument.

* I have been both amused and infuriated that this issue still haunts us. I understand why American fundamentalists who call themselves creation scientists, with their usual mixture of cynicism and ignorance, use the following argument for rhetorical advantage: (1) evolution treats the ultimate origin of life; (2) evolutionists can't resolve this issue; (3) the question is inherently religious; (4) therefore evolution is religion, and our brand deserves just as much time as theirs in science classrooms. We reply, although creationists do not choose to listen or understand, that we agree with points two and three, and therefore do not study the question of ultimate origins or view this issue as part of scientific inquiry at all (point one). I was surprised that Mr. Justice Scalia accepted this fundamentalist argument as the basis for his singularly inept dissent in the Louisiana creationism case, Edwards v. Aguillard (see Gould, 1991b).

* This tripartite structure of the Origin is masked by our tendency to treat the two geological chapters (9-10) as a unity. (Darwin even summarizes them together at the end of Chapter 10.) But Chapter 9, as the title proclaims (On the imperfection of the geological record), belongs to the discussion of difficulties in part 2 of the Origin while Chapter 10 (On the geological succession of organic beings) initiates part three on documentation of evolution as a fact. (Even the consolidated summary of Chapter 10 makes a clear break between these two disparate parts of Darwin's geological argument.)

* Later Lord Avebury and an author of many fine evolutionary works himself. But Lubbock's greatest contribution to human thought was probably indirect, a result of neighborly fellowship for he sold to Darwin a corner of property that became the famous sandwalk where Darwin, perambulating and kicking aside a flint cobble for each circumnavigation, solved several riddles of life and human existence. Darwin graded the difficulty of his problems by the number of circuits required for solution two-flint problems, five-flint problems, etc. I suspect that macroevolutionary theory must present us with at least a fifty-flint problem!

* The word adaptation did not enter biology with the advent of evolutionary theory. The Oxford English Dictionary traces this term to the early 17th century in a variety of meanings, all designating the design or suitability of an object for a particular function, the fit of one thing to another. The British school of natural theology used adaptation as a standard word for illustrating God's wisdom by the exquisite fit of form to immediate function. Darwin, in borrowing this term, followed an established definition while radically revising die cause of the phenomenon.

* Hecatomb, an unfamiliar word in English, should enter the vocabulary of all evolutionists as a wonderfully appropriate description for this key aspect of Darwinism. A hecatomb is, literally, an offering of a hundred oxen in sacrifice. Yet, even in Homer, the word had come to designate any large number of deaths incurred as a sacrifice for some intended benefit a good description of natural selection. And hecatomb trips so much more lightly off the tongue than substitutional load.

* By the syllogistic core of natural selection (the bare-bones argument), I refer to the standard pedagogical presentation of the abstract mechanism of the theory as a set of three undeniable factual statements followed by the inference of natural selection (the fourth statement) as a logical entailment of the three facts, viz:

1. Superfecundity: all organisms produce more offspring than can possibly survive.

2. Variation: all organisms vary from other conspecifics, so that each individual bears distinguishing features.

Next page
Light

Font size:

Reset

Interval:

Bookmark:

Make

Similar books «The Structure of Evolutionary Theory»

Look at similar books to The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. We have selected literature similar in name and meaning in the hope of providing readers with more options to find new, interesting, not yet read works.


Reviews about «The Structure of Evolutionary Theory»

Discussion, reviews of the book The Structure of Evolutionary Theory and just readers' own opinions. Leave your comments, write what you think about the work, its meaning or the main characters. Specify what exactly you liked and what you didn't like, and why you think so.